iBet uBet web content aggregator. Adding the entire web to your favor.
iBet uBet web content aggregator. Adding the entire web to your favor.



Link to original content: https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0223.xml
Aesthetic Hedonism - Philosophy - Oxford Bibliographies

In This Article Expand or collapse the "in this article" section Aesthetic Hedonism

  • Introduction
  • General Overviews
  • The Nature of Aesthetic Pleasure
  • Evolution and the Aesthetic Response
  • Psychology and the Aesthetic Response
  • Hedonist Tendencies
  • Antihedonist Views
  • Ahedonic Art
  • Aristotle
  • Hutcheson and Hume
  • Kant

Philosophy Aesthetic Hedonism
by
Mohan Matthen, Zachary Weinstein
  • LAST REVIEWED: 27 May 2020
  • LAST MODIFIED: 27 May 2020
  • DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0223

Introduction

Hedonism is the view that pleasure is the only thing that has final, or non-derivative, value: other things are valuable only to the extent that they produce pleasure. In this context, pleasure may be narrowly conceived as an agreeable sensation, or functionally as a psychological response that reinforces a subject’s propensity to perform the action that evokes the response. (Critics of aesthetic hedonism [AH] have often assumed the former, but criticism narrowly based on this conception does not work when leveled against a functional conception.) Either way, it makes value depend on human response, not on objective qualities. AH applies this thesis to aesthetic value, holding that it derives from aesthetic pleasure. AH runs contrary to objectivism—the idea that aesthetic value is independent of the value of experience (experience being, at most, an apprehension of value). AH starts from the fact that human beings “like” art; aesthetic value is then understood as the instrumental value of giving them what they like. However, great tragedy arouses negative emotions, and the best art is cognitively difficult to understand. These are psychological barriers to engagement and appreciation. AH must show why these barriers do not reduce value. Most aesthetic hedonists address the difficulty by delimiting the scope either of hedonism or of aesthetic pleasure. Some scholars, e.g. Hume, say that art must be valued relative to the response of somebody who has been sufficiently exposed to it, and has thus developed “taste”; only the pleasure that such subjects take in art is probative. Others, e.g. Kant, posit a special kind of pleasure characteristic of aesthetic appreciation. This, he says, is “disinterested,” and thus different from the mere “agreeability” of food and sex, and also of low art—it is, nevertheless, a form of pleasure. In other treatments, other human motivations are invoked, including emotional immersion in Indian “rasa” theory, social harmony in Confucius, forms of eroticism (an idea that traces back to Plato), Freudian negative impulses such as the death wish, and vitalistic life forces. These are not forms of hedonism in the strict sense, but they are founded on human response, and so they are anti-objectivist in tenor. More recently, ideas from other areas of philosophy—specifically philosophy of mind and value theory—have been employed for and against AH, including nontraditional ways of understanding the nature of pleasure. The authors would like to acknowledge research support from the Australian Research Council DP 150103143 as part of the research project Taste and Community led by Jennifer A. McMahon, on which Mohan Matthen was a co-investigator.

General Overviews

Van der Berg 2020 is a comprehensive review of AH, though from a critical perspective. Lopes 2018 is the only other overview specifically devoted to AH. The broad issues of hedonism (closely related to what is sometimes called “empiricism”) and aesthetic value are treated in a number of scene-setting introductory articles. The most specific treatment is Stecker 2004. Herwitz 2014 is an excellent historical treatment of aesthetic pleasure and Zangwill 2014 contains a useful discussion of how normative aesthetic judgments relate to subjective responses. Treatments of the role of pleasure in aesthetic responses to art are also embedded in Guyer 2005, Shelley 2013, and Korsmeyer 2013.

  • Guyer, Paul. “History of Modern Aesthetics.” In The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Edited by Jerrold Levinson, 25–60. New York: Oxford University Press, 2005.

    Indispensable historical overview of theories of aesthetic experience.

  • Herwitz, Daniel. “Pleasure.” In Encyclopedia of Aesthetics. 2d ed. Edited by Michael Kelly. New York: Oxford University Press, 2014.

    A survey of theories of aesthetic pleasure from European philosophy in the Early Modern period to the present.

  • Korsmeyer, Carolyn. “Taste.” In The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics. 3d ed. Edited by Berys N. Gaut and Dominic M. Lopes, 193–202. New York: Routledge, 2013.

    Discusses a variety of theories of aesthetic evaluation based on the enjoyment that an object affords to a person of good taste, thematizing the gustatory metaphor.

  • Lopes, Dominic McIver. “To Seize upon the Applause of the Heart.” In Being for Beauty: Aesthetic Agency and Value. By Dominic McIver Lopes, 53–70. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018.

    Though embedded within a book that argues against AH, this chapter is a sympathetic stand-alone overview of AH.

  • Shelley, James. “Empiricism: Hutcheson and Hume.” In The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics. 3d ed. Edited by Berys N. Gaut and Dominic M. Lopes, 37–49. New York: Routledge, 2013.

    Historical introduction to views in British empiricism that ground aesthetic value in the experience that objects evoke.

  • Stecker, Robert. “Value in Art.” In The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics. Edited by Jerrold Levinson, 307–324. New York: Oxford University Press, 2004.

    General introduction to questions of value in art, including an excellent discussion of theories based on aesthetic experience, more generally, and those based on pleasure.

  • van der Berg, Servaas. “Aesthetic Hedonism and Its Critics.” Philosophy Compass 15.1 (2020): e12645.

    DOI: 10.1111/phc3.12645

    An excellent entry point into the subject. According to the author, AH is the “dominant view of aesthetic value.” This assessment rests on a broad conception of pleasure-based response. Though the author believes that its “privileged status . . . is detrimental to downstream research,” he gives a remarkably fair and thorough treatment.

  • Zangwill, Nick. “Aesthetic Judgment.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Stanford, CA: Stanford University, 2014.

    Discusses judgments of beauty and other aesthetic qualities, discussing in particular the centrality of pleasure and of reactions to it.

back to top

Users without a subscription are not able to see the full content on this page. Please subscribe or login.

How to Subscribe

Oxford Bibliographies Online is available by subscription and perpetual access to institutions. For more information or to contact an Oxford Sales Representative click here.

Article

Up

Down