WTJ 78 (2016): 249–69
THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN SCOTUS AND TURRETIN
IN THEIR FORMULATION OF THE
DOCTRINE OF FREEDOM
B. Hoon Woo
I
n their contribution to The Reformed Thought on Freedom: The Concept of
Free Choice in Early Modern Reformed Theology, E. Dekker, A. J. Beck, and
T. T. J. Pleizier contend that although Turretin is not an innovator among
Reformed thinkers on the doctrine of freedom, he contributes two things to
the discussion: irst, Turretin expands the discussion on necessity; second,
he introduces a multi-layered concept of indiference. Their assessment of
Turretin is basically correct, but more can be said regarding Turretin’s diferences with Scotus on the concepts of necessity and indiference. The authors
fail to show where Turretin difers from Scotus in the doctrine of freedom and
even appear to regard Turretin’s position as the same as that of Scotus on this
issue.1 The present article, however, will argue that Turretin’s explanation of
freedom difers from that of Scotus, and that Turretin accomplished his aim
by developing the concepts of necessity and indiference. It will show that the
diference between Scotus and Turretin can be observed clearly in their reception of Aristotle’s work regarding this issue.
This study will proceed chronologically. The irst section will examine
Aristotle’s conception of freedom in Int. 9, which is cited in Scotus’s Lect. 1.39,
and in Eth. nic. 3 and 6, which are quoted in Turretin’s Institutes, Tenth Topic.2
B. Hoon Woo is Professor of Dogmatics and Dean of the Department of Theology at Kosin University in Busan,
South Korea.
1 Eef Dekker, Andreas J. Beck, and T. Theo J. Pleizier, “Beyond Indiference: An Elenctic Locus
on Free Choice by Francesco Turrettini (1623–1687),” in The Reformed Thought on Freedom: The
Concept of Free Choice in Early Modern Reformed Theology, ed. Willem J. van Asselt, J. Martin Bac, and
Roelf T. te Velde (Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2010), ch. 6, here pp. 195–200.
2 The literature related to Aristotle’s conception of freedom includes Lambertus Marie de
Rijk, Aristotle: Semantics and Ontology (Leiden: Brill, 2002); Michael Frede and Gisela Striker, eds.,
Rationality in Greek Thought (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996); Roderick T. Long, “Aristotle’s
Conception of Freedom,” The Review of Metaphysics 49 (1996): 775–802; Gisela Striker, Essays on
Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996); Jonathan Barnes,
ed., The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995); Timothy D.
J. Chappell, Aristotle and Augustine on Freedom: Two Theories of Freedom, Voluntary Action, and Akrasia
(New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1995); Richard Sorabji, Animal Minds and Human Morals: The Origins
of the Western Debate (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993); Pamela M. Huby, “Review: Aristotle and
249
250
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
Van Asselt, Bac, and te Velde are inclined to think that Aristotle only argues
for “diachronic contingency,” which means “a contingency with change and a
necessity with changelessness.” They seem to regard Aristotle as a determinist.
This article shows, however, that Aristotle also holds to “synchronic contingency,” which implies that “for one moment of time, there is a true alternative
for the state of afairs that actually occurs.”3 The second section, after a short
survey of the reception of Aristotle in the Middle Ages,4 will deal with Scotus’s
reception of Aristotle in his formulation of the doctrine of freedom. Antonie
Vos argues that Scotus created the concept of synchronic contingency in western intellectual history.5 Knuuttila also points to a very similar view.6 Harm
Goris, however, argues that Vos and Knuuttila’s interpretations of Aristotle and
Scotus are lawed at several points.7 An assessment of this issue exceeds the
scope of this article and needs further research. Rather, the present study will
Determinism,” Classical Review, n.s., 41 (1991): 370–71; Michael Frede, Essays in Ancient Philosophy
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987); Gail Fine, “Aristotle on Determinism: A Review
of Richard Sorabji’s Necessity, Cause, and Blame,” Philosophical Review 90 (1981): 561–79; Richard
Sorabji, Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle’s Theory (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,
1980); Michael J. White, “Aristotle’s Temporal Interpretation of Necessary Coming-to-Be and
Stoic Determinism,” Phoenix 34 (1980): 208–18; Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm Schoield, and Richard
Sorabji, eds., Articles on Aristotle (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1978).
3 Van Asselt, Bac, and te Velde, eds., Reformed Thought on Freedom, 41.
4 Burgess Laughlin, The Aristotle Adventure: A Guide to the Greek, Arabic, and Latin Scholars Who
Transmitted Aristotle’s Logic to the Renaissance (Flagstaf, AZ: Albert Hale, 1995); Norman Kretzmann,
Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg, eds., The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy: From
the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600 (New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1982); Fernand van Steenberghen, Thomas Aquinas and Radical Aristotelianism
(Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1980); Lambertus Marie de Rijk, Middeleeuwse
wijsbegeerte: Traditie en vernieuwing (Assen: Van Gorcum, 1977); Fernand van Steenberghen, La
Philosophie au XIIIe Siecle (Louvain: Publications Universitaires, 1966); Lambertus Marie de Rijk,
Logica Modernorum: A Contribution to the History of Early Terminist Logic (Assen: Van Gorcum, 1962);
René Antoine Gauthier and Jean Yves Jolif, eds., L’éthique à Nicomaque: Introduction, traduction, et
commentaire (Louvain: Publications Universitaires, 1958); Fernand van Steenberghen, Aristotle in the
West: The Origins of Latin Aristotelianism (Louvain: E. Nauwelaerts, 1955); Fernand van Steenberghen,
The Philosophical Movement in the Thirteenth Century (Edinburgh: Nelson, 1955).
5 Duns Scotus, Contingency and Freedom: Lectura I 39, ed. Antonie Vos (Boston: Kluwer Academic,
1994), 5–6, 20–33, and passim; Antonie Vos, The Philosophy of John Duns Scotus (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2006), 39–40; Antonie Vos and Andreas J. Beck, “Conceptual Patterns Related to
Reformed Scholasticism,” NedTT 57 (2003): 223–33; Antonie Vos, Kennis en Noodzakelijkheid: Een
kritische analyse van het absolute evidentialisme in wijsbegeerte en theologie, Dissertationes Neerlandicae
5 (Kampen: Kok, 1981); Joachim Roland Sölder, Kontingenz und Wissen: Die Lehre von den “futura
contingentia” bei J. Duns Scotus (Münster: Aschendorfsverlag, 1999).
6 Simo Knuuttila, Modalities in Medieval Philosophy (New York: Routledge, 1993); Simo Knuuttila,
Reforging the Great Chain of Being: Studies of the History of Modal Theories (Hingham, MA: D. Reidel,
1981).
7 Harm J. M. J. Goris, Free Creatures of an Eternal God: Thomas Aquinas on God’s Foreknowledge and
Irresistible Will (Leuven: Peeters, 1996); Harm J. M. J. Goris, “Reception of Aristotle’s De Interpretatione
9 in the Latin West: Boethius and the Scholastics,” Verbum 6, Yearbook of the Center of Studies of
Medieval Culture at St Petersburg State University (2002): 63–70.
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
251
focus on Scotus’s reception of Aristotle in his formulation of the doctrine of
freedom, and will explain the deinition of synchronic contingency. The third
section will deal with Turretin’s reception of Aristotle in his formulation of the
doctrine of freedom. Dekker, Beck, and Pleizier endorse Vos’s idea and apply
it to their study of Turretin. They argue that Turretin’s doctrine of freedom is
the same as that of Scotus in that both of them explain the doctrine with the
help of the concept of synchronic contingency. They contend that “Turrettini
utilizes the scholastic distinction between in sensu composito and in sensu diviso
in the synchronic, Scotist reading.”8 Turretin, however, seems to say more than
that. This article will show that Turretin’s doctrine of freedom cannot be fully
explained by the synchronic, Scotist reading.9 It will also demonstrate that
Scotus and Turretin difer in their reception of Aristotle as they formulate their
respective doctrines of freedom, and that because of this diference, Turretin’s
view on freedom difers from Scotus’s formulation.
I. Aristotle’s Understanding Of Freedom in De interpretatione 9
and Ethica nicomachea 3 and 6
1. Aristotle: Determinist or Indeterminist?
Aristotle’s conception of freedom can be observed most clearly in Int. 9; Eth.
nic. 3 and 6; Metaphysica, 6.2, 3 and 9.5; De generatione et corruptione, 2.11; De
partibus animalium, 1.1; and Physica, 2.9. There have been heated exchanges
concerning whether Aristotle was a determinist or not. In Cicero’s De fato 39,
Aristotle is considered, in a certain sense, a determinist. Cicero holds that the
ancient philosophers are divided into two parties on the doctrine of fate. Some
philosophers maintain that everything is made by fate so that fate exerts a
necessary force over everything (omnia ita fato ieri, ut id fatum vim necessitatis
adferret). Other philosophers hold that fate has no inluence whatsoever over
the voluntary acts of the soul. Aristotle belongs to the former party. Cicero
lists Aristotle with three pre-Socratic philosophers (Democritus, Heraclitus,
and Empedocles), who were well-known determinists in ancient times. Cicero
argues that for Aristotle the movements of the soul are caused by external forces
which amount to fate. That is why he regards Aristotle as a determinist. Donini
argues that Cicero’s main source is not the work of Antiochus but the work
of Carneades via Clitomachus. He also holds that Cicero might have added
8
Dekker, Beck, and Pleizier, “Beyond Indiference,” 195.
The main thesis of this article sides in essence with Paul Helm’s idea concerning synchronic
contingency, although this article, unlike those of Helm, will demonstrate the thesis from a more
fundamental perspective based on a close reading of Aristotle’s works. See Paul Helm, “Synchronic
Contingency Again,” NedTT 57 (2003): 234–38; Helm, “Synchronic Contingency in Reformed
Scholasticism: A Note of Caution,” NedTT 57 (2003): 207–22; Helm, “Reformed Thought on
Freedom: Some Further Thoughts,” Journal of Reformed Theology 4, no. 3 (2010): 185–207.
9
252
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
Aristotle’s name without referring to his works.10 However, Cicero’s sources, by
which he classiies Aristotle as a determinist, are still debated. There are other
ancient scholars who depict Aristotle as an indeterminist. In the third century
AD, for example, Alexander of Aphrodisias labeled him an indeterminist. In
his De fato 10 and 11, Alexander classiies Aristotle as an indeterminist, based
on Aristotle’s Eth. nic. 3.3.1112a21f.11
The issue of whether Aristotle is a determinist still occupies scholars. Loening
lists nineteen modern commentators who provide an indeterministic interpretation.12 However, Loening himself and Gomperz support the deterministic
interpretation.13 In a more recent contribution to the discussion, Hintikka, the
main proponent of the so-called Helsinki school, provides a modiied deterministic interpretation.14 There are extreme indeterminist interpretations such as
those ofered by Preus, Kullmann, Wieland, Düring, Sambursky, Weiss, Balme,
and Ross.15 Sorabji deals with the views of these scholars and concludes that
Aristotle is an indeterminist.16 The notion of determinism itself is varied among
scholars. Some scholars tend to deine it with reference to causation; others
deine it with reference to necessity.17 Considerable work needs to be done to
compare the views of modern scholars before a conclusion can be reached
regarding whether Aristotle was a determinist or not. In keeping with the stated
purpose, this article will be limited to the study of Int. 9, cited by Scotus in his
10
Pierluigi Donini, Ethos: Aristotele e il determinismo (Alessandria: Dell’Orso, 1989), 134–35.
R. W. Sharples, trans., Alexander of Aphrodisias on Fate: Text, Translation, and Commentary (London:
Duckworth, 1983), 53–57, 134–42.
12 Richard Loening, Die Zurechnungslehre des Aristoteles ( Jena: Gustav Fischer, 1903; repr.,
Whiteish, MT: Kessinger, 2010), ch. 18, nn. 2, 3, 4.
13 Theodor Gomperz, Greek Thinkers: A History of Ancient Philosophy, trans. Laurie Magnus and
George Godfrey Berry (New York: Scribner, 1912), vol. 4, chs. 10, 16.
14 Jaakko Hintikka, Time and Necessity: Studies in Aristotle’s Theory of Modality (Oxford: Clarendon,
1973), chs. 5, 8, 9; Jaakko Hintikka, Unto Remes, and Simo Knuuttila, Aristotle on Modality and
Determinism, Acta Philosophica Fennica 29, no. 1 (Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing, 1977).
15 Anthony Preus, Science and Philosophy in Aristotle’s Biological Works, Studien und Materialien
zur Geschichte der Philosophie, Kleine Reihe, 1 (Hildesheim: G. Olms, 1975), ch. 4; Wolfgang
Kullmann, Wissenschaft und Methode: Interpretationen zur aristotelischen Theorie der Naturwissenschaft
(Berlin: de Gruyter, 1974), 292–93, 337; Wolfgang Wieland, Die aristotelische Physik: Untersuchungen
über die Grundlegung der Naturwissenschaft und die sprachlichen Bedingungen der Prinzipienforschung
bei Aristoteles (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1962), 264–66; Ingemar Düring, “Aristotle’s
Method in Biology,” in Aristote et les problèmes de méthode: Communications présentées au Symposium
Aristotelicum tenu à Louvain du 24 août au 1er septembre 1960 (Louvain: Publications Universitaires,
1961), 215; Samuel Sambursky, Physics of the Stoics (New York: Macmillan, 1959), 71–73; Helene
Weiss, Kausalität und Zufall in der Philosophie des Aristoteles (Basel: Verlag Haus zum Falken, 1942),
75–93; Helene Weiss, Der Zufall in der Philosophie des Aristoteles (London: Wyndham Printers, 1942),
75–93; D. M. Balme, “Greek Science and Mechanism: I. Aristotle on Nature and Chance,” ClQ
33, no. 3 (1939): 134; William David Ross, Aristotle’s Physics: A Revised Text with Introduction and
Commentary (Oxford: Clarendon, 1936), 43.
16 Sorabji, Necessity, Cause, and Blame, x. Sorabji argues that Aristotle believes that causal necessity
and teleology are compatible, but he denies that Aristotle believes that causal necessity and responsibility are compatible.
17 Ibid., ix.
11
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
253
Lect. 1.39, and Eth. nic. 3 and 6, cited by Turretin in his Institutes, Tenth Topic.
The study of these passages of Aristotle will show to some extent how this theme
is being unveiled. It should be noted, however, that Int. 9 and Eth. nic. 3, 6 are
concerned with very diferent matters, which will be explained below.
2. Aristotle on Freedom in De interpretatione 9
In Int. 9, Aristotle deals with future contingent events (contingentia futura).
He seems to refute here the Megarian philosophers, Diodorus Cronus (d. c. 284
BC) and Philo the Dialectician (l. 300 BC), who deduced determinism from
the law of contradiction.18 De interpretatione 9 is divided into three parts.19 In
the irst part (18a28–34), Aristotle argues that “with regard to what is and what
has been it is necessary for the airmation or the negation to be true or false”
(18a28–29).20 In the second part (18a34–19a6), he proves that if the previous
law is applied to “particulars that are going to be,” one cannot help but fall
into determinism.21 In the third part (19a7–19b4), he rejects the determinism
of the second part and presents his own explanation about this subject matter.
This third part is the kernel of Aristotle’s argument in Int. 9. Aristotle holds:
What is, necessarily is, when it is; and what is not, necessarily is not, when it is not.
But not everything that is, necessarily is; and not everything that is not, necessarily is
not. For to say that everything that is, is of necessity, when it is, is not the same as
saying unconditionally that it is of necessity. Similarly with what is not. And the same
account holds for contradictories: everything necessarily is or is not, and will be or
will not be; but one cannot divide and say that one or the other is necessary.22
This passage is Aristotle’s most famous treatment of determinism, and many
commentators have studied it.23 Hermann Weidemann devotes one third of
his commentary on De interpretatione to this chapter, and Richard Gaskin has
presented the most detailed analysis of the whole debate on the text.24 There
18 Concerning the history of the interpretation of Int. 9, see Aristotle, Categories and De interpretatione, translated with notes by J. L. Ackrill (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 138–42;
Aristotle, Peri hermeneias, ed. Hermann Weidemann (Berlin: Akademie, 2002), 300–324.
19 The critical editions of De interpretatione and Nicomachean Ethics used here are Aristotle,
Aristotelis Categoriae et liber De interpretatione, ed. Lorenzo Minio-Paluello, Scriptorum classicorum
bibliotheca Oxoniensis (Oxford: Clarendon, 1956) and Aristotle, Ethica Nicomachea, ed. Ingram
Bywater, Scriptorum classicorum bibliotheca Oxoniensis (Oxford: Clarendon, 1894).
20 Aristotle, The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), 28; hereafter cited as Works. The translations of
Aristotle’s works are quoted from this book except where noted otherwise.
21 Ibid., 28–29.
22 Ibid., 30 (19a23–29).
23 For an annotated bibliography for this passage, see Vincenza Celluprica, Il capitolo 9 del “De
interpretatione” di Aristotele: Rassegna di studi, 1930–1973 (Rome: Il Mulino, 1977).
24 Weidemann, Peri hermeneias; Richard Gaskin, The Sea Battle and the Master Argument: Aristotle
and Diodorus Cronus on the Metaphysics of the Future, Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie 40 (Berlin:
de Gruyter, 1995).
254
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
are four interpretations of this passage.25 The irst interpretation is called
“traditional” or “standard” (Hintikka), “orthodox” (Rescher), “oldest”
(Kretzmann), or “anti-realist” (Gaskin). This view claims that Aristotle airms
unconditionally that every proposition is either true or not true (the law of
excluded middle). In this view, however, Aristotle limits the validity of the idea
that every proposition is true or false (the law of bivalence) because he knows
that there would be another possibility in the case of sentences about future
contingencies. This view maintains that Aristotle either accepts a valued logic
with the truth values “true,” “false,” and “neuter” or admits that sentences
about future contingencies have no truth value at all.
The second interpretation is labeled “non-standard” (Hintikka), “medieval”
(Rescher), “second oldest” (Kretzmann), or “realist” (Gaskin). It holds that
Aristotle identiies the law of excluded middle with the law of bivalence, claiming that he saw both as universally valid. In this view, however, Aristotle denies
some kind of necessity to the truth value of sentences about future contingencies. Sentences about future contingencies are true or false, but not necessarily;
they are only contingently true or contingently false.
The third interpretation is the so-called “statistical” interpretation, represented by Hintikka and Knuuttila.26 This view holds that Aristotle is speaking
about the temporally indeinite sentences in Int. 9. The reference of the temporally indeinite sentences depends on the moment the sentence is uttered.
Thus their truth value may change over time. For Hintikka and Knuuttila,
Aristotle maintains that contingency is suiciently assured when the temporally
indeinite sentences are not supposed to be always true. Hintikka and Knuuttila
argue that the strategy of the Aristotle of their interpretation is philosophically
unconvincing.27
The fourth view is suggested by Harm Goris. He stresses the role of temporal
indeiniteness, which is endorsed by the third view.28 He argues that the sentence, “There will be a sea battle on Saturday, November 8, 2014,” uttered on
Friday, November 7, 2014, difers both linguistically and logically from the
sentence, “There is a sea battle on Saturday, November 8, 2014,” uttered on
Saturday, November 8, 2014. Both sentences must express or signify diferent
propositions. Each of the two temporally indeinite sentences becomes relatively temporally deinite with regard to the other because their truth value is
decided by the time when the sentence is pronounced. The sentences, “There
will be a sea battle tomorrow” and “There will not be a sea battle tomorrow”
25
I owe the following explanation to Goris, “Reception of Aristotle’s De Interpretatione 9,” 8–9.
Hintikka, Remes, and Knuuttila, Aristotle on Modality and Determinism; Simo Knuuttila,
“Medieval Commentators on Future Contingents in De Interpretatione 9,” Vivarium 48 (2010): 75–95.
27 Many scholars do not accept the statistical interpretation of Hintikka and Knuuttila (see
Goris, “Reception of Aristotle’s De Interpretatione 9,” 66, 68).
28 For modern philosophy of time, see L. Nathan Oaklander and Quentin Smith, eds., The New
Theory of Time (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994); Quentin Smith and L. Nathan Oaklander,
Time, Change, and Freedom: An Introduction to Metaphysics (New York: Routledge, 1995).
26
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
255
are contradictory only if they are uttered at roughly the same moment. Goris
argues that Thomas Aquinas implies this idea when Thomas claims that the
sentence, “It rained yesterday, and it doesn’t rain today,” does not constitute
a contradiction.29 Sentences about the future can have a diferent truth value
according to the time of utterance. Goris is convinced that this interpretation
shows most clearly what Aristotle means.
Each of these four interpretations has strengths and weaknesses.30 It is noted,
however, that none of the four interpretations deinitively refutes the notion of
future contingency. The irst and second views were endorsed by the ancient
interpreters and the medieval interpreters respectively. Both of them stress the
concept of future contingency in their interpretation of Int. 9. It seems that
Aristotle clearly assumes the notion of future contingency when he holds:
I mean, for example, it is necessary for there to be or not to be a sea-battle tomorrow; but it is not necessary for a sea-battle to take place tomorrow, nor for one not
to take place—though it is necessary for one to take place or not to take place. So,
since statements are true according to how the actual things are, it is clear that
wherever these are such as to allow of contraries as chance has it, the same necessarily
holds for the contradictories also. This happens with things that are not always so or
are not always not so. With these it is necessary for one or the other of the contradictories to
be true or false—not, however, this one or that one, but as chance has it; or for one to be true
rather than the other, yet not already true or false.
Clearly, then, it is not necessary that of every airmation and opposite negation one
should be true and the other false. For what holds for things that are does not hold for
things that are not but may possibly be or not be; with these it is as we have said.31
With the help of the terminology of medieval theology, it can be argued that
Aristotle distinguishes here between the necessity of the consequent [thing]
(necessitas consequentis) and the necessity of the consequence (necessitas
consequentiae).32 The necessity of the consequent means the absolute necessity
of something that cannot be other than what it is. The necessity of the consequence means a logical necessity which applies to the implication between
two events. It explains the connection of necessary causes from which the effects must follow. Aristotle appears to refute determinism which denies future
contingency. He argues that “there would be no need to deliberate or to take
trouble,” if everything is and happens of necessity (18b30–31). For him, “not
everything is or happens of necessity” (19a18–19).33
29
Aquinas, In I Peri herm. lect. 9, no. 117 (lines 149–150 in the Leonine ed.).
Concerning the weak points of the irst three views, see Goris, “Reception of Aristotle’s De
Interpretatione 9,” 65–66.
31 Aristotle, Works, 30 (19a30–b4) (emphasis mine).
32 Van Asselt, Bac, and te Velde, eds., Reformed Thought on Freedom, 34–38; Kretzmann, Kenny,
and Pinborg, Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, 342–81; Richard A. Muller, Dictionary of
Latin and Greek Theological Terms: Drawn Principally from Protestant Scholastic Theology (Grand Rapids:
Baker, 1985), 200.
33 Thus, the compatibilistic interpretation of Fine, who distinguishes between absolute necessitarian determinism and the determinism of her Aristotle, is unconvincing (Fine, “Aristotle on
30
256
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
3. Aristotle on Freedom in Nicomachean Ethics 3 and 6
Aristotle’s Int. 9 involves not merely logico-grammatical or logico-epistemological issues, but implies metaphysical (the open future), ethical (free choice),
and theological (divine foreknowledge and prophecy) questions. Its main
focus, however, is on the logico-epistemological and metaphysical issues. By
contrast, Aristotle’s Eth. nic. 3.2 (1111b4–11112a17), 3.5 (1113b3–1114b25),
and 6.2 (1139a17–b13), which are cited in Turretin’s Institutes, are more concerned with ethical problems.
In Eth. nic. 3.2, Aristotle speaks about decision (prohairesis)34: what it is
not (1111b4–1112a13); and that decision is reached through deliberation
(1112a13–17).35 Aristotle argues that “decision is clearly something voluntary,
but is not the same thing as the voluntary, for the voluntary is a wider type”
(1111b7–8). This means that what is decided-for is voluntary (hekousion). For
Aristotle, both children and animals are voluntary, but they do not decide their
actions. Every responsible act is voluntary, but not conversely. Things done on
the spur of the moment are voluntary, but not done from decision. Actions that
have been decided-for, or responsible actions, are a subclass of the voluntary.
Decision is reached after all things are considered, and this happens most
obviously through deliberation (bouleusis). Thus decision is, at any rate, what
has been reached by prior deliberation (probebouleumenon, 1112a15).36 Aristotle
claims that even the name (prohairesis) indicates that what we decide to do
is chosen (haireton) before (pro) other things (1112a16–17). In any decision,
deliberation is presupposed. For Aristotle, deliberation precedes decision, and
actions that have been decided-for are a subclass of the voluntary. Deliberate
actions, therefore, can also be voluntary. The main aim of Eth. nic. 3.5 is to
show that persons of poor character are not just passive recipients of their
dispositions. He holds:
Thus, excellence depends on us, and similarly badness as well. For when acting depends on us (eph’hēmin), not acting does so too, and when saying no does so, saying
yes does too; so that if acting, when it is a ine thing to act, depends on us (eph’hēmin),
not acting also depends on us (eph’hēmin) when it is shameful not to act, and if not
acting, when it is a ine thing not to act, depends on us (eph’hēmin), acting when it is
a shameful thing to act also depends on us (eph’hēmin).37
Determinism,” 571–72, 575). She argues that Aristotle is a compatibilist who sees no incompatibility
between freedom and necessity and between voluntariness and necessity (p. 575).
34 Other translators have used “choice,” “rational choice,” “purpose,” for Aristotelian prohairesis.
See Broadie’s article on “Decision” (prohairesis) in Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, commentary by
Sarah Broadie, trans. Christopher Rowe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 42–46.
35 For the division of sections and commentary, see ibid., 314.
36 This sentence is expressed as a question, but it shows Aristotle’s view (ibid, 315).
37 Aristotle, Works, 1758; Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 129–30 (1113b6–12).
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
257
For Aristotle, ethical dispositions are voluntary because they depend on us
(eph’hēmin), which means that we do not just acquire something regardless
of our voluntariness. He argues that voluntary actions have an internal origin
(archē en hēmin) and are up to us, or are in our power (eph’hēmin). It is notable
that Aristotle stresses the phrase “up to us” (eph’hēmin) in order to claim that
we have moral responsibility.38 Aristotle’s arguments progress as follows: good
actions depend on us (1113b3–6); then if the good ones depend on us, so must
the bad (1113b6–14); therefore, it depends on us whether we are good or bad;
further, if we deny badness to be voluntary, we imply the absurdity that we are
not the source and begetter of our actions (1113b16–21); that this is absurd is
shown by the practices of punishment and reward (1113b21–30).39 From these
arguments, it seems reasonable to conclude that, for Aristotle, not only is the
future contingent, but the present is also contingent at least in moral issues.40
Aristotle argues in Eth. nic. 6.2 that one must understand the characteristic
of something in order to know the excellence of that something. He claims:
In the soul, the things determining action and truth are three: perception, intelligence,
and desire. But of these, perception is not an originator of any sort of action; and this
is clear from the fact that brute animals have perception but do not share in action.
What airmation and denial are in the case of thought, pursuit and avoidance are with
desire; so that, since excellence of character is a disposition issuing in decisions, and decision
is a desire informed by deliberation, in consequence both what issues from reason must
be true and the desire must be correct for the decision to be a good one, and reason
must assert and desire pursue the same things.41
Practical truth turns out to be nothing other than a right decision (prohairesis),
since it is the function of practical thinking or deliberation to arrive at this. In
a good or right decision the thought and the desire are each as they should
be, respectively, true and right.42 Decision is either desiderative thought or
intellectual desire, and human beings are originators of this sort of decision
(1139b4–5).43 Aristotle argues that decision is a combination of either thought
(dianoia) or intelligence (nous) with desire (orexis) concerning the same thing.
Thus he calls decision the appetitive intelligence (he orektikos nous) or the intelligent appetite (he orexis dianoētikē, 1139b4–5). In the subsequent passages,
38
Sorabji emphasizes rightly the importance of this “up to us” (eph’hēmin) (Sorabji, Necessity,
Cause, and Blame, 235).
39 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 319.
40 Antonie Vos says, “According to Aristotle only the future is contingent” (Scotus, Lectura I 39,
45). However, Eth. nic. 3.5 shows that for Aristotle both the present and the future are contingent.
41 Aristotle, Works, 1798 (1139a17–31) (emphasis mine); Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 177.
42 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 361–62.
43 Broadie comments on the last sentence that “there may be an implicit contrast not only with
brutes, but with god. If god is an eicient cause, then god’s efects are necessary (cf. Eudemian
Ethics II.6, 1222b20–3), and they are unmediated by discursive thought” (Broadie’s commentary
in Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 364).
258
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
Aristotle holds that “nothing that happened in the past is subject to decision
—e.g. no one decides to have sacked Troy; for no one deliberates about the
past, but rather about what is to come and contingent, whereas it is not possible
for what has happened not to have happened” (1139b5–9, emphasis mine).
For Aristotle, what is future is contingent, but what is past is not contingent. He
believes, like the ifth-century tragedian Agathon, that it is not possible even
for a god to undo things that have once been done.44 It should be stressed,
however, that for Aristotle what is future is contingent.
II. Scotus’s Reception of Aristotle in His Formulation of the
Doctrine of Freedom in Lectura 1.39
1. The Purpose of Scotus’s Lectura 1.39 and the “Synchronic Contingency”
The translations of the entire works of Aristotle were completed and became
available to scholars by the year 1200.45 Aristotle, among philosophers, was
the greatest of the auctores.46 The word philosophus is used by Scotus to denote
Aristotle,47 as is his practice with other terms of denotation like Commentator
(=Averroes), Apostolus (=Paul), and Veritas (=Christ).48 Scotus deals with Aristotle’s
Int. 9 in his formulation of the doctrine of freedom in Lect. 1.39. The Lectura is
a lecture note prepared for a course, and it is a text not yet given as opposed to
one already delivered. Scotus gave the lecture, Lect. 1.39, during 1297–1299 to
refute the view that everything is necessary and immutable.49
Scotus claims that the aim of this lecture has two points (Lect. 1.39.31): irst,
to consider the contingency in what is (de contingentia in entibus); second, to
consider how God’s certain knowledge is compatible with the contingency
of things. To argue his assertions, Scotus develops, as A. Vos puts it, the idea
44 Fine writes, “Aristotle does sometimes say that the past is necessary; but he never, to my knowledge, explicitly says that this is a type of absolute necessity. And at one place (De Int. 19a23–26)
he seems explicitly to deny that it is” (Fine, “Aristotle on Determinism,” 569). In these passages
(Eth. nic. 1139b5–9), however, Aristotle appears to believe the past belongs to a type of absolute
necessity. De interpretatione 19a23–26 also should be interpreted, as the present study puts it, with the
distinction between the necessity of the consequent thing (necessitas consequentis) and the necessity of
the consequence (necessitas consequentiae). The passage (Int. 19a23–26) does not support Fine’s idea.
45 On the translation and commentary of Aristotle in the Middle Ages, see van Steenberghen,
Aristotle in the West, 62; Kretzmann, Kenny, and Pinborg, Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy,
74–79.
46 Marie-Dominique Chenu, “Les ‘Philosophes’ dans la philosophie chrétienne médiévale,”
RSPT 26 (1957): 27–40.
47 On auctoritas (authority) and auctoritates in the Middle Ages, see §§ 4.3–4.8 (AN AUCTORITATES CULTURE) in de Rijk, Middeleeuwse wijsbegeerte; Lambertus Marie de Rijk, La philosophie au
moyen âge (Leiden: Brill, 1985), 87–105; Vos, Philosophy of John Duns Scotus, 530–33.
48 Vos, Philosophy of John Duns Scotus, 512. When Scotus uses the plural noun philosophi, it denotes
a speciic group of thinkers. In Lect. 1.8, Scotus explicitly includes Aristotle, Plato, Avicenna, and
Averroes among philosophi.
49 Scotus, Lectura I 39, 5–6, 11.
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
259
of “synchronic contingency.”50 Scotus tries to defend the validity of Christian
theology against the attack of ancient philosophers. The main argument is unpacked in Lect. 1.39.49–53.51 Scotus argues that a necessary being (God) is able
to have contingent knowledge, and that although this knowledge is contingent,
it is not necessarily mutable and temporal by that very fact.52 Vos and other
scholars claim that Scotus’s notion of synchronic contingency is “the splendid
discovery,” “logical and ontological innovations,” and “a radical alternative”
in history.53 This notion, however, seems to be found even in Aristotle’s works.
The passages in which Scotus deals with Aristotle’s Int. 9 will prove its presence
in Aristotle.
2. Scotus’s Reception of Aristotle’s De interpretatione 9 in His Lectura 1.39
In Lect. 1.39.1, Scotus asks “whether God has determinate knowledge of
things according to every aspect of their existence, as according to being in
the future.”54 He presents a counterview which claims that God cannot have
determinate knowledge of the future. To support this counterview, Aristotle’s
Int. 9 is presented as follows:
[§1] For according to the Philosopher in his book Peri hermeneias there is no determinate truth in contingent propositions about the future. Therefore, there is no
knowability either which requires determinate truth. [§2] And this is conirmed by
the following argument of the Philosopher: if there were determinate truth in those
[propositions about the future], “there would be no need to negotiate or to deliberate.” Therefore, no intellect has certain knowledge of contingent propositions. [§3]
Furthermore, one component of a contradiction concerning propositions about
the future is as indeterminate as the other. Therefore, if God knows that one component of a contradiction is determinately true, then He knows that the other is
true too, for his knowledge would be limited, if He had certain knowledge of one
component only and so no knowledge of the other.55
Aristotle’s Int. 9 is cited here as an auctoritas. In the following arguments, Scotus
does not attempt to contradict Aristotle. He does not airm or reject the ideas
of Aristotle. The only issue he argues against is the proposition that God cannot
have determinate knowledge of the future. Scotus appears to try to demonstrate
fully that Aristotle’s text is not contradictory to the Christian doctrine of God.
50
For this idea, see ibid., 23–33.
In his comment on Lect. 1.39 (p. 28), Vos says that the idea of synchronic contingency is
unfolded in Lect. 1.39.49–52, 54; in Vos, Philosophy of John Duns Scotus, p. 4, he mentions that the
notion is found in Lect.1.39.49–53. It is notable that Scotus deals with diachronic contingency in
Lect.1.39.53. I will return to this issue below.
52 Scotus, Lectura I 39, 22; van Asselt, Bac, and te Velde, eds., Reformed Thought on Freedom, 41.
53 Scotus, Lectura I 39, 6; Vos, Philosophy of John Duns Scotus, viii; van Asselt, Bac, and te Velde,
eds., Reformed Thought on Freedom, 41.
54 Scotus, Lectura I 39, 44–45. The translation of Scotus’s work is quoted from this book except
where noted otherwise.
55 Ibid., 44, 46.
51
260
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
In Lect. 1.39.55, Scotus presents Aristotle’s idea in the objection as follows:
[Objections]—But against this position it is argued that it is not possible that the will
can not-will something for that moment and at that moment at which it is willing it,
because the Philosopher says in Peri hermeneias I: “Everything which is, when it is, is
necessary.”56
This objection is composed from Aristotle’s thesis in Int. 9.19a23–24. As stated
above, there are four major interpretations about Int. 9.19a23–24. Scotus also
tries to explain it in Lect. 1.39.58, and his explanation is very similar to the second
interpretation among the four interpretations. Scotus distinguishes between
the necessity of the consequent (necessitas consequentis) and the necessity of the
consequence (necessitas consequentiae), which is parallel to the distinction between the necessity of the concomitant and the necessity of the concomitance.
He also endorses the modal logic of in sensu composito and in sensu diviso. The
analysis of modal sentences such as one sees in Scotus’s Lect. 1.39.58 was a very
common method in the Middle Ages. The distinction between in sensu composito
or in sensu diviso is also called the distinction between de dicto (or de sensu) and
de re. This modal logic originated from Aristotle’s Sophistici elenchi, 166a22–30.
For Aristotle, the meaning of a statement can change according to whether its
elements are understood in a conjoined or a divided meaning.57 The sentence,
“a sitting man can run,” is false when the possibility is understood to qualify
the conjunction of two mutually exclusive predicates with the same subject at
the same time. It can be true, however, that a man who is sitting can run after
he stops sitting. Aristotle argues that a temporally unqualiied modal sentence
can be true or false according to a temporal distinction between the action at
the same time (in sensu composito) and the action at diferent times (in sensu
diviso).58 Scotus endorses Aristotle’s distinction between the simultaneity and
non-simultaneity of the actualization of two predicates. He develops the notion
with both logical and temporal connectives, but his conception is essentially
the same as that of Aristotle.
In Lect. 1.39.49–53, Scotus explains the so-called synchronic contingency.
There he shows how the meaning of a statement changes according to readings
in sensu composito or in sensu diviso. Scotus claims:
[§51] We must distinguish the composite and the divided sense (Et est distinguenda
secundum compositionem et divisionem). It is false in the composite sense, as we understand the predicate to be attributed to this whole: the will willing at a, together with
the possibility operator. The proposition is true, however, in the divided sense; not
because we understand the terms for diferent times (that sense is relevant because
56
Ibid., 130.
Kretzmann, Kenny, and Pinborg, Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, 347, 355–57;
Knuuttila, Reforging the Great Chain of Being, 221; Hintikka, Time and Necessity, 139, 145; Knuuttila,
Modalities in Medieval Philosophy, 84–86, 167–75.
58 Kretzmann, Kenny, and Pinborg, Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, 347.
57
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
261
there is succession in acts), but it is true in the divided sense because there are two
propositions, because it implicitly includes two propositions. In one proposition the
will is said to have the act of willing, and in the other one the will is said to have the
opposite act taken on its own with the possibility operator, and then the meaning is:
The will is willing at a and The will can be not-willing at a. This is true, for the will willing
at a, freely elicits an act of willing, which is not its attribute.59
This argument is typically Aristotelian and basically coincides with the argument of Aristotle’s Int. 9. After saying that “what is, necessarily is, when it is; and
what is not, necessarily is not, when it is not” (Int. 9.19a23–24), Aristotle directly
added, “but not everything that is, necessarily is; and not everything that is not,
necessarily is not” (Int. 9.19a24–25). If the opponents of Scotus support their
claim with the passage of Int. 9.19a23–24, Scotus himself argues against them
with the passage of Int. 9.19a24–25. In doing so Scotus applies Aristotle’s notion
of the future contingency to explain the will of God about future events. Scotus
is not inventing a totally new concept here; he is applying an old concept to a
new subject matter. Moreover, Scotus himself introduces diachronic elements
into his contingency theory. He holds:
[§53] [How God’s will is the cause of contingency]—But let us now proceed to the
divine freedom.
The divine will is free to produce opposite efects. However, this freedom is not
the prime one, but requires another which is prior. The divine will, however, cannot
have the prime freedom (prima libertas) which is in us (the one with respect to opposite acts), because this one has some imperfection and involves mutability. The
divine will can only have one single volition and therefore it can will opposite objects by one single volition (voluntas autem divina non potest habere nisi unicam volitionem, et ideo unica volitione potest velle opposita obiecta). For this single volition prevails
over all created volitions with respect to diverse [objects], just as his single act of
knowing prevails over all acts of knowing of creatures. Hence, his one volition prevails over all volitions which tend to diverse objects, because any volition of ours is
limited to its object. Therefore, if one unlimited volition, which is the divine one, is
assumed, then that can be related to opposite objects. Therefore the freedom of the
divine will can relate to opposite objects by one and the same volition and is ininitely freer than we are with diverse volitions.60
Scotus argues that God wills with one single volition (unica volitione) whatever
he wills. God has one volition ad intra, but this one volition can be related to
many opposite things ad extra. God can simultaneously will one thing at time
1 and the opposite thing at time 2. Thus, Scotus’s theory of contingency has a
diachronic aspect as well as a synchronic aspect.
In light of this observation, it is hard to agree with Vos’s description of
Aristotle and Scotus. He calls Aristotle’s theory of contingency “diachronic
contingency.” He argues that in Aristotle’s model, contingency means “nothing
59
60
Scotus, Lectura I 39, 118.
Ibid., 124.
262
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
other than change through time.” In the contingency of Aristotle, as Vos puts
it, “things that change are not contingent at all.”61 Along these lines, van Asselt,
Bac, and te Velde also hold that in Aristotle’s theory of contingency “on each
moment, only one state of afairs occurs without any alternative.”62 Vos argues
that a theory of real contingency was not fully formulated until Scotus’s Lect.
1.39. He contends that real contingency, which was conceived by Scotus, implies
that “the opposite is possible for the same moment,” and he calls this contingency synchronic.63 Van Asselt, Bac, and te Velde also agree with Vos. They
argue that only Scotus’s idea of synchronic contingency can account for real
freedom of choice, both on God’s part and on our part.64 Vos, van Asselt, Bac,
and te Velde sharply distinguish the idea of contingency in Aristotle from that
of Scotus. Along similar lines, Knuuttila argues that the modal theory of Duns
Scotus is incompatible with the Aristotelian modal paradigm which he calls “the
statistical interpretation of modality.”65 In his recent article, however, Knuuttila
says that there are various possible interpretations of Aristotle’s Int. 9.66 He
even concedes that John Buridan (ca. 1300–1362) thought that the Scotistic
contingency theory was an Aristotelian view.67 Buridan’s judgment is all the
more possible because of at least four reasons: (1) Aristotle’s Int. 9.19a23–25
can be interpreted like the Scotistic contingency theory; (2) Scotus himself
does not refute Aristotle’s Int. 9 in Lect. 1.39.49–53; (3) Scotus, rather, tries to
formulate his contingency theory with the help of other works of Aristotle in
Lect. 1.39.51, 54; (4) Scotus introduces the diachronic feature of God’s volition
to his contingency theory as well as the synchronic feature. Thus, Vos’s reading
of Scotus seems unconvincing. Furthermore, it is quite improbable that, as
Dekker, Beck, and Pleizier state, Turretin’s doctrine of freedom is a Scotist view.
The following section will demonstrate this assessment.
III. Turretin’s Reception of Aristotle in His Formulation of the Doctrine of
Freedom in Institutes of Elenctic Theology, Tenth Topic
1. The Content and Purpose of Turretin’s Tenth Topic
The Tenth Topic of Turretin’s Institutes presents the doctrine of freedom.68
Turretin deals with human freedom in relation to sin which is the subject of the
61
Ibid., 24–25.
Van Asselt, Bac, and te Velde, eds., Reformed Thought on Freedom, 41.
63 Scotus, Lectura I 39, 25.
64 Van Asselt, Bac, and te Velde, eds., Reformed Thought on Freedom, 41.
65 Knuuttila, Reforging the Great Chain of Being, 221.
66 Knuuttila, “Medieval Commentators on Future Contingents,” 76–77.
67 Ibid., 75–76, 92.
68 Francis Turretin, Institutes of Elenctic Theology, ed. James T. Dennison, trans. George Musgrave
Giger (Phillipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian & Reformed, 1992), 659–85; Dekker, Beck, and Pleizier,
“Beyond Indiference,” 171–200. Herein the translations of the Latin Institutio (Geneva, 1679) are
quoted from the above two works with some corrections of mine.
62
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
263
Ninth Topic.69 He delves into the question of how the human will was afected
by the fall. Turretin examines the change in the relationship between God and
humans after the fall.
Turretin unpacks this doctrine in ive major questions: he argues that free
choice belongs to both the intellect and the will (Question 1); against the
papists and Remonstrants, he contends that not every necessity is repugnant
to freedom of the will (Question 2); against the papists, Socinians, and Remonstrants, he argues that the formal deinition of free will consists not in indiference but in rational spontaneity (Question 3); against the papists, Socinians,
and Remonstrants, he holds that the free will in a state of sin is so a servant of
and enslaved by sin that it can do nothing but sin, and that it does not have the
power to incline itself to good, not only regarding civil and external morality,
but also internal and spiritual good (Question 4); against the papists, he denies
that the virtues of the heathen are good works from which the power of free
will to do good can be inferred (Question 5).
Along the lines of Reformed theology, Turretin argues that after the fall
human beings did not lose the faculty of will itself. “The inability to do good is
strongly asserted, but the essence of freedom is not destroyed” (Inst. 10.2.9).
They still have liberty which is not repugnant to certain kinds of necessity.
Turretin distinguishes six kinds of necessity (Inst. 10.2.4–9): physical necessity,
necessity of coercion, necessity of dependence on God, rational necessity, moral
necessity, and necessity of event. The irst two among these six necessities are
incompatible with freedom, whereas the latter four are not only compatible
with freedom but perfect it. For Turretin, freedom does not arise from an
indiference of the will. No rational beings are indiferent to good and evil. The
will of an individual human being is never indiferent in the sense of possessing
an equilibrium, either before or after the fall. Turretin deines freedom with
the notion of rational spontaneity (Inst. 10.2.10–11).
2. Turretin’s Reception of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics in Institutes, Tenth Topic
Turretin cites Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics four times in his Tenth Topic.70 In
Inst. 10.1.4, Turretin argues that the subject of free choice is both the intellect
and the will. The subject of free choice belongs to the intellect with regard to
69
Dekker, Beck, and Pleizier, “Beyond Indiference,” 173.
For “Christian Aristotelianism” of early modern Reformed theology, see Richard A. Muller,
Post-Reformation Reformed Dogmatics: The Rise and Development of Reformed Orthodoxy, ca. 1520 to ca.
1725, 4 vols. (Grand Rapids: Baker, 2006), 1:360–82; Richard A. Muller, “Reformation, Orthodoxy,
‘Christian Aristotelianism,’ and the Eclecticism of Early Modern Philosophy,” Nederlands Archief voor
Kerkgeschiedenis 81 (2001): 306–25. Early modern Reformed theologians opted for philosophical
eclecticism and regarded traditional “Christian Aristotelianism” as relevant for theological studies.
They did not, however, adhere to the philosophy of Aristotle himself. For them Aristotelianism
was not a ixed body of doctrines, but a collection of methods and contents that was passed on by
tradition. Thus their Aristotelianism belonged to a “generic Aristotelian tradition.” See B. Hoon
70
264
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
the choice or decision (prohairesis), and it belongs to the will with regard to
freedom. Turretin calls the subject of free choice a mixed faculty or a wedlock
(connubium) and meeting of both the intellect and the will. However, it is not
appropriate to say that it consists in both faculties, because as the choice of the
intellect is terminated in the will, so the freedom of the will has its root in the
intellect (Sicut enim arbitrium intellectus terminatur in voluntate; Ita libertas voluntatis radicem habet in intellectu). In search of a basis for his argument, Turretin is
led to Aristotle. He believes that for this reason the philosopher [Philosophus,
Aristotle], leaving this an open question, calls decision either the appetitive
intelligence (he orektikos nous) or the intelligent appetite (he orexis dianoētikē) in
Eth. nic. 6.2.1139b4–5.71 Turretin cites Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics positively,
and endorses it as an authority.
Turretin advances his argument and asserts that the intellect and will are
mutually connected and never can be separated from each other (Inst. 10.1.5).
It seems to him that there is no real and intrinsic distinction between the intellect and will, but only an extrinsic distinction with regard to the objects. It is
called “intellect” when it is occupied in the knowledge and judgment of things,
but “will” when it is carried to love or hatred. Here Turretin quotes Eth. nic.
6.2.1139a21–22, where Aristotle says, “What airmation and denial are in the
case of thought, pursuit and avoidance are with desire.” With these arguments,
Turretin ofers a basis for his discussion about indiference (Inst. 10.3).
In Inst. 10.2.4, Turretin deals with six necessities. The ifth is a moral necessity
or necessity of servitude, which arises from good or bad habits. Turretin holds
with Aristotle’s Eth. nic. 3.5 that when our will is imbued with moral habits, our
moral habits cannot be trained nor be laid aside ([sc. habitus morales] neque non
exerceri neque deponi possint). In Eth. nic. 3.5, Aristotle tries to show that persons
of poor character are not just passive recipients of their dispositions. Ethical
dispositions are voluntary because they are “in our power” (eph’hēmin). We do
not just acquire or ind ourselves with one regardless of what we voluntarily
do. Aristotle argues that good and bad actions are in our power (1113b3–14).72
Along the lines of Aristotle, Turretin is convinced that the will, which is free in
itself, is determined either to good or to evil, and that it cannot but act either
well or badly.
The fourth passage in which Turretin cites Aristotle is in Inst. 10.3.10. Turretin claims that the formal deinition of freedom (ratio formalis libertatis)73 is
Woo, “The Understanding of Gisbertus Voetius and René Descartes on the Relationship of Faith
and Reason, and Theology and Philosophy,” WTJ 75 (2013): 55–56; Aza Goudriaan, Reformed
Orthodoxy and Philosophy, 1625–1750: Gisbertus Voetius, Petrus Van Mastricht and Anthonius Driessen,
Brill’s Series in Church History 26 (Leiden: Brill, 2006), 36, 54.
71 Turretin, Institutes, 715. Turretin mentions “Ethi. l.5.c.2,” but it denotes Eth. nic. 6.2.
72 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 319.
73 Dekker, Beck, and Pleizier, “Beyond Indiference,” 192n36: “The formal or essential deinition difers from a notiication of all essential properties of a certain object; ‘able to laugh,’ for
instance, is an essential property of a human person, but does not belong to its formal deinition.”
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
265
not placed in indiference (indiferentia) and should be sought only in rational
willingness (lubentia rationali). Thus both the decision (to prohairetikon) and
the willingness (to ekousion) must be joined together to constitute the formal
deinition of freedom. What is freely done is not done by a blind impulse, but by
decision. It is done without coercion. Turretin appeals to Aristotle (Philosophus),
who calls decision “a prior deliberation” (probebouleumenon, 1112a15). In so doing Turretin refutes the notion of active indiference and argues that the formal
reason of free will consists not in indiference but in rational spontaneity. In the
four passages in which Turretin cites Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, he endorses
Aristotle’s ideas to support his argument. He rightly understands Aristotle’s
theses and appropriately applies them to formulate the doctrine of freedom.
3. Turretin’s Reception of Aristotelian Logic in the Tenth Topic
Besides the above four passages Turretin endorses Aristotelian logic twice in
Inst. 10.2.10 and 10.3.4. Turretin holds in Inst. 10.2.10:
Fourthly, the necessity of event [does not destroy freedom of choice]. For although
whatever that is, necessarily is, when it is, so that it could no more not be; still it is said
to happen no less freely or contingently as depending upon free or contingent
causes. For the certainty and truth of the existence of a thing cannot change
its essence.74
Turretin cites here the irst part of Aristotle’s sentence in Int. 9.19a23–24: What
is, necessarily is, when it is; and what is not, necessarily is not, when it is not.
His subsequent explanation is typically an Aristotelian distinction between the
necessity of the consequent [thing] (necessitas consequentis) and the necessity of
the consequence (necessitas consequentiae).
Turretin elaborates his deinition of indiference (indiferentia or adiaphora)
with the help of Aristotle’s distinction between in sensu diviso and in sensu
composito. He holds in Inst. 10.3.4:
Hence it is evident that it is not inquired here concerning indiference in the irst
act or in a divided sense, i.e., with respect to the simultaneity of potency (simulates
potentiae), which is called passive and objective indiference. [So the question is not]
whether the will, considered absolutely in its natural constitution and the requisites
for acting being withdrawn, is determinable to various objects and holds itself indifferently towards them. For we do not deny that the will of itself is so related [to its
objects] that it can either elicit or suspend the act, which is the freedom of exercise
and of contradiction or can be carried to each one of opposite [acts], which is the
freedom of contrariety and of speciication. We also confess that the will is indiferent as long as the intellect remains doubtful and uncertain whither to turn itself.
But the question is about indiference in the second act and in a composite sense,
i.e., with respect to the potency of simultaneity (potentia simultatis), which is called
74
Turretin, Institutes, 664 (emphasis mine).
266
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
active and subjective indiference. [So the question indeed is] whether the will, all
requisites for acting being posited; for example, the decree of God and his concourse; the judgment of the practical intellect, etc. is always so indiferent and undetermined that it can act or not act. This is pretended by our opponents in order that
its own freedom may be left to the will. We deny it.75
Turretin endorses Aristotle’s modal logic which became a paradigm in medieval
and early modern theology. He adopts only the irst meaning of indiference,
which is deined in the divided sense, and rejects the second meaning of indifference. Turretin argues that in the divided sense of indiference the will can
be carried to each one of the opposite acts. Thus, the notion of indiference
in the divided sense implies the so-called synchronic contingency. It is not appropriate, however, to call Turretin a Scotist regarding this issue, as Dekker,
Beck, and Pleizier do.76 Turretin takes no heed of Scotus in this passage. He
follows the basic logic of the Aristotelian tradition. He appears to be a Scotist
just because he endorses the typical Aristotelian logic. Rather, Turretin is not
a Scotist for various reasons as evidenced below. As Paul Helm points out, the
idea of Scotus here is not so diferent from Thomas’s idea in Summa Theologiae,
1a.14.9.77 There Thomas argues that “it is not necessary that all that God knows
should exist at some time, past, present or future, but only such things as he
wills to exist or permits to exist. And again, it is no part of God’s knowledge that
such things should exist, but that they could exist.”78
IV. The Diference between Scotus and Turretin in
Their Doctrines Of Freedom
1. The Diference between Scotus and Turretin in their Understandings of Necessity
The main concern of Scotus in his Lect. 1.39 lies in the question about
whether God has determinate knowledge for the future. Scotus’s opponents
appeal to Aristotle’s Int. 9, which seems to claim determinism about the future.
Scotus argues, with the help of Aristotelian logic, that God can have determinate knowledge for the future. By contrast, Turretin deals with the function and
limitation of the free choice of an individual human being in a state of sin. He
begins by arguing that freedom of choice belongs to both the intellect and the
will. He diferentiates the six kinds of necessity and argues that human freedom
of choice can be compatible with the four necessities as he deines them. Turretin’s argument about necessity makes a striking contrast to Scotus’s doctrine
of freedom. Turretin develops this argument because his major concern is not
the freedom of God but the human freedom of choice.
75
Ibid., 665–66 (emphasis mine).
Dekker, Beck, and Pleizier, “Beyond Indiference,” 195.
77 Helm, “Synchronic Contingency in Reformed Scholasticism,” 210–11.
78 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, trans. Thomas Gilby (London: Eyre & Spottiswoode,
1969), 34.
76
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
267
Question 4 deals with the freedom of humanity in the state of sin which is to
be considered as the second state according to the Augustinian tradition. In his
Enchiridion, chapter 118, Augustine distinguishes the four states of humanity:
the irst state in which humans were able to sin and not to sin (posse peccare et non
peccare); the second state after the fall and before conversion in which humans
are not able not to sin (non posse non peccare); the third state after the fall and
after conversion in which humans are able not to sin (posse non peccare); the
fourth state of glory (status gloriae) in which humans are not able to sin (non
posse peccare). Turretin argues that human beings cannot please God in the
second state.
2. The Diference between Scotus and Turretin in Their Understandings of Indiference
Along these lines Turretin refutes the conception of indiference in the
Jesuit, Socinian, and Remonstrant theology. It should be noted that the Jesuit,
Socinian, and Remonstrant view as described by Turretin looks remarkably like
that of Scotus as evidenced by his Ordinatio 2. In Ord. 2, Distinction 41, Scotus
discusses the issue of indiferent acts. He concludes:
There are many indiferent acts, therefore, which are such not merely because of
the being they have as a speciic nature, but also according to the being they have as
something moral. And there are also acts that are indiferent as regards the goodness that is meritorious or the evil that is demeritorious, for one individual good can
be of this sort and another of that sort. Many individual elicited acts can also be indifferent, because they are neither the meritorious sort nor the other, and we are not
speaking here of nonhuman acts, such as stroking the beard or brushing of a bit of
straw and suchlike, acts which originate with the sense imagination and not from
any free impulse, for freely elicited acts can also be indiferent.79
Scotus’s idea of indiference contrasts strongly with that of Turretin. In Inst.
10.3.5, Turretin argues:
First, such an indiference to opposite [acts] in no free agent, whether created or
uncreated: neither in God, who is most freely good indeed, yet not indiferently, as
if he could be evil, but necessarily and immutably; nor in Christ, who obeyed God
most freely and yet most necessarily because he could not sin; nor in angels and the
blessed, who worship God with the highest willingness and yet are necessarily determined to good, nor in devils and reprobates, who cannot but sin, although they sin
freely neither the constancy and immutability of the former in the good destroys,
but perfects their freedom.80
79 The selection is a translation of a revision of the Wadding ed. (1639) based on Codices A, V,
and S; cited from William A. Frank, ed., Duns Scotus on the Will and Morality, trans. Allan Bernard
Wolter (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1997), 53.
80 Turretin, Institutes, 666.
268
WESTMINSTER THEOLOGICAL JOURNAL
The diference between Scotus and Turretin in understanding the idea of indifference leads them to think diferently about the doctrine of salvation. In Lect.
1.40, Scotus is convinced that the salvation of humanity is totally contingent.
He argues that it is contingent whether a chosen person can be damned (utrum
praedestinatus posset damnari).81 In Ord. 39, Scotus holds that Judas Iscariot could
have been saved by God’s ordained power in another order he might have set
up.82 Turretin, however, is convinced that only the grace of God determines the
salvation of a human being, as can be seen in Inst. 10.4.10 (3):
That servitude does prevent man from being able to shake of the yoke of sin by his
own strength, but does not hinder him from being able to be freed from sin by free
will with the assistance of grace. We answer that it is said ambiguously that man is
able to be freed by free will with the help of God. For either it is understood of passive liberation, that the free will itself may be delivered by grace (which we grant); or
of active liberation, by which the free will applies itself to the assisting grace of God
and by its own powers (although not alone) cooperates with it (which we deny).83
The salvation of a human being is determined by the grace of God at least in
the initial stage of the work of salvation. It is not a contingent matter whether
an individual human being is saved or not. Turretin argues that “the work of
our conversion is a creation, resurrection, regeneration and the production
of a new heart by which God not only gently persuades but powerfully efects
in us to will and to do” (Inst. 10.4.21). In his description of the initial stage of
salvation, therefore, Turretin’s theology does not leave any room for either
contingency or synergism.
V. Conclusion
Turretin’s doctrine of freedom appears to be similar to that of Scotus in that
both of them endorse Aristotelian logic: the distinction between the necessity
of the consequent (necessitas consequentis) and the necessity of the consequence
(necessitas consequentiae); the distinction between in sensu composito and in sensu
diviso. It is not Scotus’s notion of synchronic contingency but Aristotle’s modal
logic that is incorporated into Turretin’s doctrine of freedom. Moreover, the
Scotistic ideas about necessity and indiference difer greatly from those of
Turretin. Turretin develops the discussion on necessity and relates it to his
argument about human freedom of choice. His careful rejection of the notion of indiference in the doctrine of freedom creates a big gap between his
doctrine and that of Scotus. Turretin’s teaching of contingency emphasizes
81
Scotus, Lectura I 39, 27n53.
Frank, Duns Scotus on the Will and Morality, 193–94.
83 Turretin, Institutes, 671–72.
82
SCOTUS AND TURRETIN ON FREEDOM
269
the sovereign act of God in the process of conversion, whereas Scotus’s contingency theory blurs it. Turretin is not a Scotist, but a Reformed theologian
standing in a more “generic Aristotelian tradition.”84
84
For the conception, see n. 70.