iBet uBet web content aggregator. Adding the entire web to your favor.
iBet uBet web content aggregator. Adding the entire web to your favor.



Link to original content: https://unpaywall.org/10.1007/978-3-030-29007-8_15
Epistemic Reasoning with Byzantine-Faulty Agents | SpringerLink
Skip to main content

Epistemic Reasoning with Byzantine-Faulty Agents

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Frontiers of Combining Systems (FroCoS 2019)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNAI,volume 11715))

Included in the following conference series:

Abstract

We introduce a novel comprehensive framework for epistemic reasoning in multi-agent systems where agents may behave asynchronously and may be byzantine faulty. Extending Fagin et al.’s classic runs-and-systems framework to agents who may arbitrarily deviate from their protocols, it combines epistemic and temporal logic and incorporates fine-grained mechanisms for specifying distributed protocols and their behaviors. Besides our framework’s ability to express any type of faulty behavior, from fully byzantine to fully benign, it allows to specify arbitrary timing and synchronization properties. As a consequence, it can be adapted to any message-passing distributed computing model we are aware of, including synchronous processes and communication, (un-)reliable uni-/multi-/broadcast communication, and even coordinated action. The utility of our framework is demonstrated by formalizing the brain-in-a-vat scenario, which exposes the substantial limitations of what can be known by asynchronous agents in fault-tolerant distributed systems. Given the knowledge of preconditions principle, this restricts preconditions that error-prone agents can use in their protocols. In particular, it is usually necessary to relativize preconditions with respect to the correctness of the acting agent.

...By our remembrances of days foregone

Such were our faults, or then we thought them none.

W. Shakespeare,

All’s Well That Ends Well

R. Kuznets—Supported by the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) project RiSE/SHiNE (S11405) and ADynNet (P28182).

K. Fruzsa—PhD student in the FWF doctoral program LogiCS (W1255).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The term “byzantine” originated from [18]. Leslie Lamport chose a defunct country to avoid offending anyone living and also as a pun [26, p. 39] because generals from Byzantium could, in fact, be expected to behave in a byzantine (i.e., devious or treacherous) fashion. Unfortunately, this pun might be responsible for the ensuing unnecessary ([27]) capitalization of the word even for faults unrelated to Byzantium proper.

  2. 2.

    Cf. “And whatsoever else shall hap to-night, Give it an understanding but no tongue.” W. Shakespeare, Hamlet, Act I, Scene 2.

  3. 3.

    \({}:{}\)’ stands for concatenation.

  4. 4.

    Prohibition (b) does not extend to actions, which need not be correctly recorded.

  5. 5.

    In for byzantine sends or in for correct ones that will be actually performed (see filtering stage 2).

  6. 6.

    Arguments for are redundant here but will be used in future extensions.

  7. 7.

    Full definitions of and are presented in Appendix in Definition 16.

  8. 8.

    For connections to the semantic externalism and a survey of philosophical literature on the subject, see [25].

References

  1. Ben-Zvi, I., Moses, Y.: Agent-time epistemics and coordination. In: Lodaya, K. (ed.) ICLA 2013. LNCS, vol. 7750, pp. 97–108. Springer, Heidelberg (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-36039-8_9

    Chapter  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Ben-Zvi, I., Moses, Y.: Beyond Lamport’s happened-before: On time bounds and the ordering of events in distributed systems. J. ACM 61(2), 13 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1145/2542181

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Castañeda, A., Gonczarowski, Y.A., Moses, Y.: Unbeatable consensus. In: Kuhn, F. (ed.) DISC 2014. LNCS, vol. 8784, pp. 91–106. Springer, Heidelberg (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-45174-8_7

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  4. Dwork, C., Moses, Y.: Knowledge and common knowledge in a Byzantine environment: Crash failures. Inf. Comput. 88(2), 156–186 (1990). https://doi.org/10.1016/0890-5401(90)90014-9

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Ezekiel, J., Lomuscio, A.: Combining fault injection and model checking to verify fault tolerance, recoverability, and diagnosability in multi-agent systems. Inf. Comput. 254(2), 167–194 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ic.2016.10.007

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Fagin, R., Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y., Vardi, M.Y.: Reasoning About Knowledge. MIT Press, Cambridge (1995)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Fagin, R., Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y., Vardi, M.Y.: Common knowledge revisited. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 96, 89–105 (1999). https://doi.org/10.1016/S0168-0072(98)00033-5

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Fedoruk, A., Deters, R.: Improving fault-tolerance by replicating agents. In: AAMAS 2002, pp. 737–744. ACM (2002). https://doi.org/10.1145/544862.544917

  9. Fruzsa, K.: Hope for epistemic reasoning with faulty agents! In: Proceedings of ESSLLI 2019 Student Session (2019, to appear)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Gonczarowski, Y.A., Moses, Y.: Timely common knowledge: Characterising asymmetric distributed coordination via vectorial fixed points. In: Schipper, B.C. (ed.) TARK XIV, pp. 79–93 (2013). https://arxiv.org/pdf/1310.6414.pdf

  11. Goren, G., Moses, Y.: Silence. In: PODC 2018, pp. 285–294. ACM (2018). https://doi.org/10.1145/3212734.3212768

  12. Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y.: Knowledge and common knowledge in a distributed environment. J. ACM 37(3), 549–587 (1990). https://doi.org/10.1145/79147.79161

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y., Waarts, O.: A characterization of eventual Byzantine agreement. SIAM J. Comput. 31(3), 838–865 (2001). https://doi.org/10.1137/S0097539798340217

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Hintikka, J.: Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions. Cornell University Press, Ithaca (1962)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Kalech, M., Kaminka, G.A.: On the design of coordination diagnosis algorithms for teams of situated agents. Artif. Intell. 171(8–9), 491–513 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1016/j.artint.2007.03.005

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Kraus, S., Lehmann, D.: Knowledge, belief and time. Theor. Comput. Sci. 58, 155–174 (1988). https://doi.org/10.1016/0304-3975(88)90024-2

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Kuznets, R., Prosperi, L., Schmid, U., Fruzsa, K., Gréaux, L.: Knowledge in Byzantine message-passing systems I: Framework and the causal cone. Technical report TUW-260549, TU Wien (2019). https://publik.tuwien.ac.at/files/publik_260549.pdf

  18. Lamport, L., Shostak, R., Pease, M.: The Byzantine Generals Problem. ACM Trans. Program. Lang. Syst. 4(3), 382–401 (1982). https://doi.org/10.1145/357172.357176

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Lomuscio, A., Qu, H., Raimondi, F.: MCMAS: A model checker for the verification of multi-agent systems. In: Bouajjani, A., Maler, O. (eds.) CAV 2009. LNCS, vol. 5643, pp. 682–688. Springer, Heidelberg (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-02658-4_55

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  20. McKinsey, M.: Skepticism and content externalism. In: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2018). https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism-content-externalism/

  21. Michel, R.: A categorical approach to distributed systems, expressibility and knowledge. In: Rudnicki, P. (ed.) PODS 1989, pp. 129–143. ACM (1989). https://doi.org/10.1145/72981.72990

  22. Moses, Y.: Relating knowledge and coordinated action: The knowledge of preconditions principle. In: Ramanujam, R. (ed.) TARK 2015, pp. 231–245 (2015). https://doi.org/10.4204/EPTCS.215.17

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  23. Moses, Y., Shoham, Y.: Belief as defeasible knowledge. Artif. Intell. 64(2), 299–321 (1993). https://doi.org/10.1016/0004-3702(93)90107-M

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Moses, Y., Tuttle, M.R.: Programming simultaneous actions using common knowledge. Algorithmica 3, 121–169 (1988). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01762112

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Pessin, A., Goldberg, S. (eds.): The Twin Earth Chronicles: Twenty Years of Reflection on Hilary Putnam’s the “Meaning of Meaning". M. E. Sharpe (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Taubenfeld, G.: Distributed Computing Pearls. Morgan & Claypool Publishers (2018). https://doi.org/10.2200/S00845ED1V01Y201804DCT014

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  27. Trask, R.L.: Mind the Gaffe: The Penguin Guide to Common Errors in English. Penguin Books (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  28. van Ditmarsch, H.: Dynamics of lying. Synthese 191(5), 745–777 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0275-3

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Hans van Ditmarsch and Yoram Moses for extensive helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper. We also thank the anonymous reviewers for their comments and suggestions on related research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roman Kuznets .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

A Appendix

A Appendix

This section is dedicated to proving the Brain-in-a-Vat Lemma. Before engaging with the proof, we flesh out necessary details of how our framework operates.

For a function \(f :\varSigma \rightarrow \varTheta \) and a set \(X \subseteq \varSigma \) we use the following notation: . For functions with multiple arguments, we allow ourselves to mix and match elements with sets of elements, e.g., . As stated in Sect. 2, the function must be total and satisfy the following properties: for arbitrary \(i,j\in \mathcal {A}\), and , and \(a \in Actions _{i}\), and \(b \in Actions _{j}\),

  1. 1.

    ;

  2. 2.

    .

Thus, it is possible to define an inverse function on :

Definition 14

We use a function \( local :\overline{{ GHaps }_{}}\longrightarrow Haps _{}\) converting correct haps from the global format into the local ones for the respective agents in such a way that, for any \(i \in \mathcal {A}\), , and \(a \in Actions _{i}\), (1) \( local \left( \overline{ GActions }_{i}\right) = Actions _{i}\); (2) \( local \left( \overline{ GEvents }_{i}\right) = Events _{i}\); (3)  .

Recall that \( \overline{ GEvents }_{i}\cap \overline{ GEvents }_{j}=\varnothing \) for \(i\ne j\),

and . While for correct haps, \( local \) provides a translation to local format on a hap-by-hap basis, the same cannot be extended to all haps because system events from \( SysEvents _{i}\) and byzantine actions do not correspond to any local hap, to be recorded in i’s history. Thus, the localization function \(\sigma \) is defined on sets of global haps:

Definition 15

We define a localization function :

Thus, as intended, for any \(E \in \overline{ GEvents }_{i}\), the local record left by \({\mathop { fake }\left( i,E\right) }\) for agent i is the same as the record of E, whereas for any \(A'\in \overline{ GActions }_{i}\) and any , the local record of \({\mathop { fake }\left( i,A\mapsto A'\right) }\) for i is the same as that of \(A'\), whichever action A was taken in reality.

Definition 16

We abbreviate and for a tuple of performed events \(X_\epsilon \subseteq GEvents _{}\) and actions \(X_i \subseteq \overline{ GActions }_{i}\) for each \(i \in \mathcal {A}\). Given a global state \( r_{}\left( t\right) = \bigl (r_{\epsilon }\left( t\right) , r_{1}\left( t\right) , \dots , r_{n}\left( t\right) \bigr ) \in \mathscr {G}\), we define agent i’s update function that outputs a new local state from \( {\mathscr {L}^{}_{i}} \) based on i’s actions \(X_i\) and events \(X_{\epsilon }\):

(note that, in transitional runs, is always used after the action ; thus, in the absence of go(i), it is always the case that \(X_i = \varnothing \)). Similarly, the environment’s state update function

outputs a new state of the environment based on events \(X_{\epsilon }\) and all actions \(X_i\): Summarizing,

The following properties directly follow from Definition 7 of the i-intervention :

Lemma 17

Let and r be an arbitrary run. Then

  1. 1.

    , i.e., removes all actions.

  2. 2.

    , i.e., never lets agent i act.

  3. 3.

    .

  4. 4.

    \(r_i(t+1) \ne r_i(t)\)   iff   .

The last two properties mean that from i’s local perspective, the intervention is imperceptible (also when agent i was unaware of the passing round in the given run).

Proof

(of Brain-in-a-Vat Lemma 8). Let . Prop. 6 follows from the definitions of and . Prop. 7 follows from (1). Prop. 8 follows from Lemma 17.1 for i and from the definitions of and for \(j\ne i\). Prop. 5 follows from (1) for i and from the definition of for \(j\in Byz\). Prop. 24 depend solely on rounds to of \(r'\), whereas the transitionality of \(r'\) for Prop. 1 from round onward directly follows from Definition 6. We now show Prop. 14 for \(m\le t\) by induction on m.

Base: \(m=0\). Prop. 34 and transitionality for Prop. 1 are trivial. Prop. 2 follows from Definition 6.

Step from m to \(m+1\) . We prove Prop. 1 based on the gullibility of i and delayability (and fallibility) of all other \(j\ne i\). In order to show that , we need to demonstrate that the \(\beta \)-sets prescribed by \( adj \) can be obtained in a regular round. Since the adversary’s choice of actions  for all \(j\in \mathcal {A}\) is immaterial due to the absence of go(j) (by Prop. 7 for i and Prop. 6 for other \(j\ne i\)), we concentrate on ensuring the adversary can choose suitable \(\alpha \)-sets of events. Consider from the original run r. The set is coherent because r is transitional. By the delayability of all \(j \ne i\), Note that for any \(Z \subseteq FEvents _{i}\), because . Thus, by the gullibility of i,

(note that this set is coherent because it contains no correct events and neither go(i) nor \({\mathop { hibernate }\left( i\right) }\)). Finally, by the fallibility of all agents \(j\in Byz\), This is coherent and unaffected by filtering (there are no correct receives in to be filtered out, and only at most f agents from \(\{i\}\sqcup Byz\) become byzantine).

It remains to show that filtering turns these sets , into the exact \(\beta \)-sets prescribed by the adjustment \( adj \). Let us abbreviate:

Our goal is to show that and for each \(j \in \mathcal {A}\). After the filtering phase, for our i and \(j\ne i\), we have the following:

the latter being exactly . Since \(go(j) \notin \varUpsilon \) for any \(j \in \mathcal {A}\), we also have that for all \(j \in \mathcal {A}\). This completes the induction step for Prop. 1.

For Prop. 2, the induction step follows from Lemma 17.34. We have:

  • if , then by IH. It remains to use Lemma 17.3 to see that the last expression is the same as

  • if but \(r_{i}\left( m+1\right) \ne r_{i}\left( m\right) \), then \( r_{i}\left( m+1\right) =\) by IH. By Lemma 17.4, we also have . Thus, this case can be concluded by using Lemma 17.3 as it was done in the previous case.

  • if and \(r_{i}\left( m+1\right) = r_{i}\left( m\right) \), then by Lemma 17.34 (note that , meaning that ). Using IH, we now immediately get,

This completes the proof of the induction step for Prop. 2.

For Prop. 34, the induction step is even simpler. Since, for any \(j \ne i,\) by Prop. 6, it follows that by IH. Similarly, by Prop. 6 for \(j \notin \{i\}\sqcup Byz\). Thus, being correct at m by IH, such agents j remain correct after round .   \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Kuznets, R., Prosperi, L., Schmid, U., Fruzsa, K. (2019). Epistemic Reasoning with Byzantine-Faulty Agents. In: Herzig, A., Popescu, A. (eds) Frontiers of Combining Systems. FroCoS 2019. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 11715. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-29007-8_15

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-29007-8_15

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-29006-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-29007-8

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics