Abstract
Classic results in computability theory concern extensional results: the behaviour of partial recursive functions rather than the programs computing them. We prove a generalisation of Rice’s Theorem concerning equivalence classes of programs and show how it can be used to study intensional properties such as time and space complexity. While many results that follow from our general theorems can - and have - been proved by more involved, specialised methods, our results are sufficiently simple that little work is needed to apply them.
A very preliminary version of this paper first appeared at the DICE ’16 workshop [12].
Access this chapter
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
- 1.
For the technical development, we need only assume \(\mathcal {P}\) to be r.e. but morally we are interested in concrete programming languages where \(\mathcal {P}\) will always be a decidable set.
- 2.
See, e.g., [8] for an easily readable account.
References
Asperti, A.: The intensional content of Rice’s theorem. In: POPL 2008 (2008)
Bellantoni, S., Cook, S.: A new recursion-theoretic characterization of the poly-time functions. Comput. Complex. 2, 97–110 (1992)
Blum, M.: A machine-independent theory of the complexity of recursive functions. J. ACM 14(2), 322–336 (1967)
Hoyrup, M.: The decidable properties of subrecursive functions. In: ICALP 2016, pp. 108:1–108:13 (2016)
Hoyrup, M.: Topological analysis of representations. In: Manea, F., Miller, R.G., Nowotka, D. (eds.) CiE 2018. LNCS, vol. 10936, pp. 214–223. Springer, Cham (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-94418-0_22
Hoyrup, M., Rojas, C.: On the information carried by programs about the objects they compute. Theory Comput. Syst. 61(4), 1214–1236 (2017)
Jones, N.D.: Computability and Complexity, from a Programming Perspective. MIT Press, Cambridge (1997)
Kahrs, S.: The primitive recursive functions are recursively enumerable. Technical report, University of Kent at Canterbury
Kirby, L., Paris, J.: Accessible independence results for peano arithmetic. Bull. Lond. Math. Soc. 14(4), 285–293 (1982)
Kreisel, G., Lacombe, D., Shoenfield, J.: Fonctionelles recursivement définissables et fonctionnelles récursives. Comptes Rendus Hebdomadaires des Séances de l’Académie des Sciences 245, 399–402 (1957)
Moschovakis, Y.: Recursive metric spaces. Fundamenta Mathematicae 55(3), 215–238 (1964)
Moyen, J.Y., Simonsen, J.G.: More intensional versions of Rice’s Theorem. In: Mazza, D. (ed.) Developments in Implicit Computational Complexity, DICE 2016, Eindhoven, Netherlands, p. 2 (2016)
Moyen, J., Simonsen, J.G.: Computability in the lattice of equivalence relations. In: Proceedings 8th Workshop on Developments in Implicit Computational Complexity and 5th Workshop on Foundational and Practical Aspects of Resource Analysis (DICE-FOPARA@ETAPS 2017), pp. 38–46 (2017)
Myhill, J.R., Shepherdson, J.C.: Effective operations on partial recursive functions. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 1, 310–317 (1955)
Ore, Ø.: Theory of equivalence relations. Duke Math. J. 9(3), 573–627 (1942)
Papadimitriou, C.H.: Computational Complexity. Addison-Wesley, Boston (1994)
Rice, H.G.: Classes of recursively enumerable sets and their decision problems. Trans. Am. Math. Soc. 74, 358–366 (1953)
Shapiro, N.: Degrees of computability. Trans. AMS 82, 281–299 (1956)
Smullyan, R.M.: Undecidability and recursive inseparability. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 4(7–11), 143–147 (1958)
Tseitin, G.: Algorithmic operators in construtive complete separable metric spaces. Dokl. Akad. Nauk 128, 49–52 (1959). (in Russian)
Tseitin, G.: Algorithmic operators in constructive metric spaces. Tr. Mat. Inst. Steklov 67, 295–361 (1962). (in Russian. English translation. In: AMS Trans. 64 (1967))
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
A Material Omitted from the Main Text
A Material Omitted from the Main Text
Proof
(Full proof of intrication from Example 3). We prove that the switching family \(( \pi _{a,b} )_{(a,b) \in (\cup F) \times (\cup G)}\) is \(\textsc {RE} \)-F-G-intricated with \(\Bumpeq _\mathtt {s}\):
If \(\mathtt {p}\in \cup F\), \(\mathtt {q}\in \cup G\) and \(T' \in \mathcal {T}\) such that \(A_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}} \subseteq \pi _{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}} ^{-1}(T')\), there are two cases:
-
If \(\phi _{\mathtt {p}} = \phi _{\mathtt {q}}\), then \(A_{\mathtt {s},\mathtt {p}} = B_{\mathtt {s},\mathtt {q}}\), and there is clearly no set separating \(A_{\mathtt {s},\mathtt {p}}\) from \(B_{\mathtt {s},\mathtt {q}}\).
-
If \(\phi _{\mathtt {p}} \ne \phi _{\mathtt {q}}\), there are again two cases:
-
If r does not halt on n, then \(\phi _{s_{r,n}} = \phi _{\mathtt {p}} = \phi _{\mathtt {s}} \in F\), and thus \((r,n) \in A_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}}\). Conversely, if \((r,n) \in A_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}}\), then \(\phi _{s_{r,n}} = \phi _{\mathtt {s}}\), and as \(\lnot (\mathtt {q}\Bumpeq \mathtt {s})\), this implies that r does not halt on n.
-
If r halts on n, then \(\phi _{s_{r,n}} \bumpeq \phi _{\mathtt {q}}\). As \(\mathtt {q}\in \cup G\), we have \(\lnot (\mathtt {q}\Bumpeq \mathtt {s})\), and thus \(\lnot (\phi _{s_{r,n}} \Bumpeq \mathtt {s})\), whence in particular \(\phi _{s_{r,n}} \ne \phi _{\mathtt {s}}\), and hence \(\phi _{s_{r,n}} \Bumpeq _\mathtt {s}\mathtt {q}\). Thus, \((r,n) \in B_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}}\). Conversely, if \((r,n) \in B_{\mathtt {p}, \mathtt {q}}\), \(s_{r,n} \Bumpeq _\mathtt {s}\mathtt {q}\) which–as \(\lnot (\mathtt {q}\Bumpeq \mathtt {p})\)–implies \(\phi _{s_{r,n}} \ne \phi _{\mathtt {s}}\) and hence that r halts on n.
Thus \((r,n) \in A_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}}\) iff r does not halt on n, and \((r,n) \in B_{\mathtt {p}, \mathtt {q}}\) iff r halts on n. Hence, \(A_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}} \cup B_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}} = \mathcal {P}\times \mathcal {N}\), and \(A_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {s}}\) are \(B_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {s}}\) is co-r.e.-complete and r.e.-complete, respectively. If there were an an r.e. set C such that \(A_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}} \subseteq C\) and \(B_{a,b} \cap C = \emptyset \), then \(A_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}} \cup B_{\mathtt {p},\mathtt {q}} = \mathcal {P}\times \mathcal {N}\) implies \(A_{a,b} = C\), whence \(A_{a,b }\) is r.e., contradicting that it is co-r.e.-complete. \(\square \)
-
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG
About this paper
Cite this paper
Moyen, JY., Simonsen, J.G. (2019). More Intensional Versions of Rice’s Theorem. In: Manea, F., Martin, B., Paulusma, D., Primiero, G. (eds) Computing with Foresight and Industry. CiE 2019. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 11558. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-22996-2_19
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-22996-2_19
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Cham
Print ISBN: 978-3-030-22995-5
Online ISBN: 978-3-030-22996-2
eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)