iBet uBet web content aggregator. Adding the entire web to your favor.
iBet uBet web content aggregator. Adding the entire web to your favor.



Link to original content: http://www.patheos.com/blogs/enigmaticmirror/2014/04/23/dh-20-historicity-2/
DH 20: Historicity 2 | William Hamblin

DH 20: Historicity 2

DH 20: Historicity 2 April 23, 2014

Historians have long realized that, epistemologically speaking, the idea of learning what “really happened” through historical methodologies is fraught with difficulties that sometimes renders a solution essentially impossible, especially with ancient history.  History is not an empirical discipline.  We cannot directly observe the past.  We can only indirectly observe the effects of the past.  These effects generally consist of man-made materials that survive from the past: texts and artifacts (including art).  Thus, historians cannot directly observe Moses.  We can only directly observe what surviving ancient texts tell about Moses, or artifacts that may survive from Moses’ day (e.g. the Midianite tent-shrine and bronze serpent images found at Timna in the Negev, dating roughly to Moses’ time).

It is very important to note here that the existence of an ancient text that talks about Moses does not prove his historicity, nor does the lack of texts discussing Moses prove he did not exist.  The reality of what did or did not exist in the ancient past is an ontological question that in many ways can never be resolved by historical methods.  The question of how we, as twenty-first century historians can know about what did or did not exist in the past is an epistemological question.  Ancient texts tell us only what the ancient author believed or thought happened—or, just as often, what the ancient author wants his readers to believe happened.  We often have ample evidence for ancient people who were completely fictitious, and also often have no evidence whatsoever for ancient realities.

Fictitious things can be said about real people, as any observer of modern American politics can readily attest.  Ancient authors often were mistaken, confused, or lied about the things they describe.  Just like people today, ancient authors often sincerely believed false things, and wrote them down as if they were true.  Ancient people, just like us, enjoyed a good story, and either told or wrote stories which we would now call historical fiction.  The classic example in antiquity is the fictitious biography of Alexander the Great by Pseudo-Callisthenes, often called the Alexander Romance.  Most of what medieval people knew (or thought they knew) about Alexander the Great actually comes from Pseudo-Callisthenes, which survives in many more manuscripts and languages than the historical biographies of Alexander.  But the fact that someone anciently wrote historical fiction about Alexander does not demonstrate that Alexander did not exist.  It can, however, from an epistemological perspective, render knowing the “real” Alexander difficult.  Likewise, the fact that someone wrote something confused, false or fictitious about Moses does not demonstrate he did or did not exist.  Ontologically speaking Moses either existed or did not exist, regardless of the quantity, nature, or date of the surviving ancient evidence about Moses.  Epistemologically speaking, if the evidence is scant, contradictory, or inaccurate, we may not be able to know that Moses existed, or, if he did, to know accurate things about him through historical methodologies.


Browse Our Archives

Follow Us!