Showing changes from revision #32 to #33:
Added | Removed | Changed
basic constructions:
strong axioms
further
A category is small if it has a small set of objects and a small set of morphisms.
In other words, a small category is an internal category in the category Set.
A category which is not small may be called large, especially when it is not essentially small (see below).
Small categories are free of some of the subtleties that apply to large categories.
A category is said to be essentially small if (or, it rarely, issvelte) if it is equivalent to a small category. Assuming the axiom of choice, this is the same as saying that it has a small skeleton, or equivalently that it is locally small and has a small number of isomorphism classes of objects.
A small category structure on a locally small category is an essentially surjective functor from a set (as a discrete category) to . A category is essentially small iff it is locally small and has a small category structure; unlike the previous paragraph, this result does not require the axiom of choice.
The following are equivalent for a locally small category (see the linked MathOverflow answer).
These different characterisations are useful, because they give a way to capture the notion of size in formal category theory. For instance, characterisation (2) is axiomatised in the formalism of small objects in Yoneda structures; whereas characterisation (5) is axiomatised in the formalism of petit objects in KZ-doctrines (see DL23).
If Grothendieck universes are being used, then for a fixed Grothendieck universe, a category is -small if its collection of objects and collection of morphisms are both elements of . Thus,
This of course is a material formulation. We may call structurally -small if there is a bijection from its set of morphisms to an element of (the same for the set of objects follows). This gives an up-to-isomorphism version of -smallness (see universe in a topos for an alternative structural formulation). Such structural -smallness may be substituted in the discussion below.
Let be the category of -small sets. Similar considerations lead us to say
and that a category essentially -small if it is locally -small and admits an essentially surjective functor from a discrete -small category.
A category is -moderate if its set of objects and set of morphisms are both subsets of . However, some categories (such as the category of -moderate categories!) are larger yet.
small category, locally small category, complete small category
Ross Street and Robert Walters, Yoneda structures on 2-categories, Journal of Algebra, Vol. 50, No. 2, 1978, pp. 350-379. []
Peter Freyd and Ross Street, On the Size of Categories, Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 1, No. 9, 1995, pp. 174-181. [[TAC](http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/volumes/1995/n9/1-09abs.html)]
Ivan Di Liberti, Fosco Loregian, Accessibility and Presentability in 2-Categories, Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra 227 1 (2023) [[arXiv:1804.08710](https://arxiv.org/abs/1804.08710), doi:10.1016/j.jpaa.2022.107155]
Seerp Roald Koudenburg, Formal category theory in augmented virtual double categories, Theory and Applications of Categories 41.10 (2024): 288-413.
Seerp Roald Koudenburg, answer to “Is every petite category essentially small?”: MathOverflow
Last revised on July 6, 2024 at 09:44:06. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.