Fred Dretske
Frederick Irwin "Fred" Dretske (/ˈdrɛtski/; December 9, 1932 – July 24, 2013) was an American philosopher noted for his contributions to epistemology and the philosophy of mind.[1]
Life and career
Born to Frederick and Hattie Dretske, Dretske first planned to be an engineer, attending Purdue University. He changed his mind after taking the university's only philosophy course, deciding philosophy was the only thing he wanted to do in his life.[2]
After graduating in 1954 with a degree in electrical engineering and serving in the army, he enrolled in graduate school in philosophy at the University of Minnesota, where he received his PhD in 1960. His dissertation, supervised by May Brodbeck, was on the philosophy of time.
Dretske's first academic appointment was to the University of Wisconsin–Madison in 1960, where he rose to the rank of full Professor. In 1988 he was recruited to Stanford University, where he was the Bella and Eloise Mabury Knapp Professor of Philosophy. He remained at Stanford until his retirement in 1998, after which he was professor emeritus in philosophy at Stanford and senior research scholar in philosophy at Duke University until his death.[2]
He was awarded the Jean Nicod Prize in 1994.[3] He was elected a Fellow of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences in 2003.[4]
Upon his death, he was survived by his second wife Judith Fortson, by his children Kathleen Dretske and Ray Dretske, and by a stepson, Ryan Fortson.[5]
Philosophical work
Dretske held externalist views about the mind, and thus he tried in various writings to show that by means of mere introspection one actually learns about their own mind less than might be expected. His later work centered on conscious experience and self-knowledge,
Seeing and Knowing (1969)
Dretske's first book, Seeing and Knowing, deals with the question of what is required to know that something is the case on the basis of what is seen. According to the theory presented in Seeing and Knowing, for a subject S to be able to see that an object b has property P is:
(i) for b to be P (ii) for S to see b (iii) for the conditions under which S sees b to be such that b would not look the way it now looks to S unless it were P and (iv) for S, believing that conditions are as described in (iii), to take b to be P.[6]
For instance, for me to see that the soup is boiling – to know, by seeing, that it is boiling – is for the soup to be boiling, for me to see the soup, for the conditions under which I see the soup to be such that it would not look the way it does were it not boiling, and for me to believe that the soup is boiling on that basis.
Knowledge and the Flow of Information (1981)
Dretske's next book returned to the topic of knowledge gained via perception but substantially changes the theory. Dretske had become convinced that information theory was required to make sense of knowledge (and also belief). He signaled this change at the beginning of the new book, opening the Preface with the lines "In the beginning there was information. The word came later."[7] Information, understood in Dretske's sense, is something that exists as an objective and mind-independent feature of the natural world and can be quantified. Dretske offers the following theory of information:
A signal r carries the information that s is F = The conditional probability of s's being F, given r (and k), is 1 (but, given k alone, less than 1).[8]
Thus, for a red light (r) to carry the information that a goal (s) has been scored (is F) is for the probability that a goal has been scored, given that the light is red (and given my background knowledge of the world, k), to be 1 (but less than 1 given just my background knowledge).
With this theory of information, Dretske then argued that for a knower, K, to know that s is F = K's belief that s is F is caused (or causally sustained) by the information that s is F.[9]
His theory of knowledge thus replaced conscious appearances with the idea that the visual state of the observer carries information, thereby minimizing appeal to the mysteries of consciousness in explaining knowledge.
Dretske's work on belief begins in the last third of Knowledge and the Flow of Information,[10] but the theory changed again in the book that followed, Explaining Behavior (1988). There Dretske claims that actions are the causing of movements by mental states, rather than the movements themselves.[11] Action is thus a partly mental process itself, not a mere product of a mental process. For the meaning – the content – of a belief to explain an action, on this view, is for the content of the belief to explain why it is that the mental state is part of a process that leads to the movement it does.[12]
Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes (1988)
According to Explaining Behavior, a belief that s is F is a brain state that has been recruited (through operant conditioning) to be part of movement-causing processes because it did, when recruited, carry the information that s is F.[13] Being recruited because of carrying information gives a thing (such as a brain state) the function of carrying that information, on Dretske's view, and having the function of carrying information makes that thing a representation.
Beliefs are thus mental representations that contribute to movement production because of their contents (saying P is why the brain state is recruited to cause movement), and so form components of the process known as acting for a reason.
An important feature of Dretske's account of belief is that, although brain states are recruited to control action because they carry information, there is no guarantee that they will continue to do so. Yet, once they have been recruited for carrying information, they have the function of carrying information, and continue to have that function even if they no longer carry information. This is how misrepresentation enters the world.[14]
Naturalizing the Mind (1995)
Dretske's last monograph was on consciousness. Between the representational theory of belief, desire, and action in Explaining Behavior and the representational theory of consciousness found in Naturalizing the Mind, Dretske aimed to give full support to what he calls the "Representational Thesis". This is the claim that:
(1) All mental facts are representational facts, and (2) All representational facts are facts about informational functions.[15]
In Naturalizing the Mind Dretske argues that when a brain state acquires, through natural selection, the function of carrying information, then it is a mental representation suited (with certain provisos) to being a state of consciousness. Representations that get their functions through being recruited by operant conditioning, on the other hand, are beliefs, just as he held in Explaining Behavior.[16]
Other philosophical work
In addition to the subjects tackled in Dretske's book-length projects, he was also known as a leading proponent, along with David Armstrong and Michael Tooley, of the view that laws of nature are relations among universals.
In his 1970 article "Epistemic Operators", Fred Dretske discusses epistemic closure and its relationship to philosophical skepticism. The principle of epistemic closure holds the following to be valid:
- S knows p.
- S knows p entails q.
- S knows q.
For example,
- John knows that he is eating oatmeal.
- John knows that eating oatmeal entails that he is not eating scrambled eggs.
- John knows that he is not eating scrambled eggs.
Epistemic closure, however, is vulnerable to exploitation by the skeptic. Eating oatmeal entails not eating scrambled eggs. It also entails not eating scrambled eggs while being deceived by an evil demon into believing one is eating oatmeal. Because John does not have evidence to suggest that he is not being deceived by an evil demon, the skeptic argues that John does not know he is eating oatmeal. To combat this attack by the skeptic, Dretske develops relevant alternatives theory (RAT).
RAT holds that an agent need only be able to rule out all relevant alternatives in order to possess knowledge.[17] According to RAT, every knowledge claim is made against a spectrum of relevant alternatives entailed by the original knowledge claim. Also entailed by a knowledge claim are irrelevant alternatives. The skeptic's alternatives fall into this irrelevant category. The following applies RAT to Johns oatmeal:
- John knows that he is eating oatmeal (as opposed to eating scrambled eggs, eating a bagel, bathing in oatmeal, etc.)
- John knows that eating oatmeal entails that he is not eating scrambled eggs.
- John knows that he is not eating scrambled eggs.
- John knows that eating oatmeal entails that he is not eating scrambled eggs while being deceived by an evil demon into believing he is eating oatmeal.
- John does not know that he is not eating scrambled eggs while being deceived by an evil demon. (This alternative is irrelevant; it does not lie within the spectrum of relevant alternatives implied by his initial claim.)
Although it provides a defense from the skeptic, RAT requires a denial of the principle of epistemic closure. Epistemic closure does not hold if one does not know all of the known entailments of a knowledge claim. The denial of epistemic closure is rejected by many philosophers who regard the principle as intuitive.
Another issue with RAT is how one defines "relevant alternatives." "A relevant alternative," Dretske writes, "is an alternative that might have been realized in the existing circumstances if the actual state of affairs had not materialized."[18]
Selected publications
- 1969, Seeing and Knowing, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-7100-6213-3
- 1981, Knowledge and the Flow of Information, Cambridge, Massachusetts The MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-04063-8
- 1988, Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes, Cambridge, Massachusetts The MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-04094-8
- 1995, Naturalizing the Mind, Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-04149-9
- 2000, Perception, Knowledge and Belief, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-77742-9
See also
References
- ^ Shook, J.R.; Hull, R.T. (2005). Dictionary of Modern American Philosophers. Vol. 1. Thoemmes Continuum. p. 660. ISBN 9781843710370. Retrieved 2015-05-13.
- ^ a b "Fred Dretske obituary". TheGuardian.com. 22 August 2013.
- ^ "Archives - INSTITUT JEAN NICOD".
- ^ "American Academy of Arts and Sciences Elects Petroski, Five Others from Duke | Duke Pratt School of Engineering". Archived from the original on 2015-07-13. Retrieved 2015-07-09.
- ^ "Frederick I. Dretske Obituary: View Frederick Dretske's Obituary by The News & Observer". legacy.com. Retrieved 2015-05-13.
- ^ Dretske (1969, pp. 78–93)
- ^ (Dretske 1981, vii)
- ^ Dretske (1981, p. 65)
- ^ Dretske (1981, p. 86)
- ^ Dretske (1981, pp. 169–235)
- ^ Dretske (1988, p. 15)
- ^ Dretske (1988, pp. 79–85)
- ^ Dretske (1988, 51–77)
- ^ Dretske (1988, pp. 64–70)
- ^ Dretske (1995, p. xiii)
- ^ Dretske (1995, pp. 2–22)
- ^ Dretske, Fred. 1970. "Epistemic Operators", The Journal of Philosophy, 67, pp. 1007–23.
- ^ Dretske (1970, p. 1021)
External links
- An Interview with Fred Dretske where colleagues ask about his work. From The Dualist, Stanford's Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy
- WHAT GOOD IS CONSCIOUSNESS?
- THE MIND'S AWARENESS OF ITSELF
- Where is the Mind when the Body Performs? Archived 2012-10-20 at the Wayback Machine
- First Person Warrant: Comments On Siewert's The Significance Of Consciousness
- Perception without Awareness
- PSYCHOLOGICAL VS. BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATIONS OF BEHAVIOR
- EXPERIENCE AS REPRESENTATION
- HOW DO YOU KNOW YOU ARE NOT A ZOMBIE?
- KNOWING WHAT YOU THINK vs KNOWING THAT YOU THINK IT, or Externalism: Thought and Their Content
- What We See, Howison Lectures in Philosophy, 14 November 2007, University of California, Berkeley
- Articles with short description
- Short description is different from Wikidata
- Webarchive template wayback links
- 1932 births
- 2013 deaths
- Action theorists
- Analytic philosophers
- American philosophers of mind
- American epistemologists
- University of Minnesota College of Liberal Arts alumni
- Duke University faculty
- 20th-century American philosophers
- 21st-century American philosophers
- Jean Nicod Prize laureates